7 Did magic matter? The saliency of magic in the early Roman empire
Introduction: the ubiquity of magic?
It is usually assumed that belief in magic was ubiquitous in the early Roman empire,[1] that, in the words of Pliny the Elder, “there is no one who does not fear to be spellbound by curse tablets”.[2] One needs only read the accounts of the famous trials for sorcery of Apollonius of Tyana[3] and Apuleius of Madaura,[4] or the magical explanations given for the untimely demise of Germanicus, Tiberius’ popular heir,[5] to see how significant magic appears to have been. Indeed, the only fully extant novel in Latin that we possess,[6] Apuleius’ Metamorphoses, is concerned with the consequences[7] of meddling in such things.[8] Homer’s Odyssey, one of the formative texts for most of the inhabitants of the empire,[9] could be thought to be “composed of nothing else”.[10] There are also a number of practical magical writings that seem to confirm much the same picture, including not just those that constitute the well-known Papyri Graecae Magicae[11] but such works as the amulet grimoire of Cyranides[12] or the Testament of Solomon — a handbook for controlling demons potentially responsible for everything from migraine to death.[13] Early Christian literature, such as the canonical Acts of the Apostles[14] and the apocryphal Acts of Peter,[15] depict an empire preoccupied by magic, a world in which those spreading the new faith are forced to battle with magicians[16] and magical books are burnt in public by those that they convert.[17]
The material culture of the empire likewise seems to provide copious, tangible evidence of the vitality of belief in magic. Artefacts, such as the myriad of defixiones (binding spells),[18] incantation bowls,[19] “voodoo” dolls,[20] magical lamellae and amulets,[21] brought together in the extensive collections by the likes of Campbell Bonner, John Gager, Roy Kotansky, Simone Michel, Daniel Ogden, and Hanna Philipp,[22] appear compelling evidence of magic’s significant place in the lives of most of its inhabitants.[23] And we could easily go on: from the presence of the paradigmatic witches Circe and Medea on Roman oil lamps, gemstones, murals and sarcophagi,[24] to the plethora of apotropaic representations of the evil eye found on everything from mosaics and amulets to ear-rings,[25] the salience of magic in the Roman Empire seems to be anything but illusory. Even epitaphs appear to bear witness to its importance. Here, for example, is one from Rome itself which dates from the 20s CE:
Iucundus, the slave of Livia the wife of Drusus Caesar, son of Gryphus and Vitalis. As I grew towards my fourth year I was seized and killed, when I had the potential to be sweet for my mother and father. I was snatched by a witch’s hand, ever cruel so long as it remains on the earth and does harm with its craft. Parents, guard your children well, lest grief of this magnitude should implant itself on your breast.[26]
Indeed, the moral and legal prohibitions placed upon magic,[27] not least the fact that the practice of magic was deemed a capital offence in Roman law,[28] combined with its prominence in early Christian heresiological literature, where it functioned “as the discourse of alterity par excellence”,[29] appears to confirm that magic was indeed a dynamic and potent force in early imperial culture. It is, perhaps, so hard to resist the intrinsic allure of an amulet depicting an anguipede, cockerel-headed Abrasax,[30] or Solomon, on horseback, spearing a demon,[31] that to conclude otherwise seems unimaginable.[32] In the face of the data we have just surveyed it could be judged perverse not to agree with Hans Dieter Betz that “Magical beliefs and practices can hardly be overestimated in their importance for the daily lives of the people.”[33]
However, the picture just drawn at best only indicates the presence of ideas about magic and magical practices of some kind, and we need to determine a defensible definition of magic before we can say even this with any confidence. Gauging the character and prevalence of magic requires a more sustained and rigorous analysis of sources that shed light on the early Roman empire, and one that, importantly, attends not just to the apparent presence of magic but its absence too. We need to note not just where it appears but also, tellingly, where it does not. Before we address these two elements of our analysis, let us begin, however, with the question of the definition of the term “magic”, something that is necessary if what follows is to have any value.
Now you see it, now you don’t: defining magic
Although “magic” at least has the advantage of being a “native category of thought” for those who lived in the Roman empire,[34] something that is not necessarily the case for the inhabitants of other cultures in the past and the present,[35] what exactly constituted “magic” for them is far from self-evident. To eschew a definition of “magic”, as some classical scholars do,[36] is not advisable because it tends to result in the conflation of “magic” with a variety of other things that might strike some modern scholars as manifestly magical but were, in fact, everyday and uncontroversial elements of religious life in the empire and not considered such by any of its inhabitants.[37] For example, divination, the attempt to determine the will of the gods and the likely outcome of future events, was not in itself something that would be judged magical by those living in the early Roman empire. It was not only ubiquitous[38] but was a central part of most religions in antiquity,[39] and especially the religious life of the Romans.[40] It is not, for example, helpful to label the activities of haruspices, many of whom were key religious officiants in the public cults of the empire, as practitioners of “oracular magic”, as some have done.[41] Such divination did not constitute magic but a respected and necessary religious act,[42] something undertaken, for instance, after most public sacrifices.[43] The same could be said of amulets or, indeed, incantations, the use of neither of which was thought in itself to be magical. For example, every freeborn male, before reaching maturity, wore a bulla, a locket hung around the neck, as an apotropaic device, often containing a representation of a phallus, but none would have considered such a thing magical.[44] Similarly, incantations were not necessarily magical activities to Romans; their use in the healing of fractures was, for example, recommended by no less a figure than Cato the Elder[45] and clearly considered by such a respectable authority to be quite distinct from magical practices proscribed under Roman law.[46]
Failing to provide a definition of magic can also lead many to inadvertently miscategorise some data, to see magic where it was patently not thought to be. For example, invocations of gods other than the Olympic pantheon and closely associated deities have often been seen as “magical” because of a historical tendency within the field to protect a dominant but narrow understanding of classical religion, to fall victim to what has been termed “Classicity”.[47] So, as Attilio Mastrocinque has demonstrated, the cult of the Askalon Asklepios has often been labelled “magical” out of ignorance of the iconography of a cult which was regarded as a local manifestation of one of the most widely dispersed and supported of all the cults in the empire, second only in significance, perhaps, to the imperial cult itself.[48]
However, avoiding a definition is perhaps understandable, if not entirely forgivable. Sarah Iles Johnston is surely right to observe that:
Endless theorizing about how magic was or was not different from religion (or anything else) had stalled our progress toward examining and understanding some fascinating ancient material.[49]
And there is good reason to sympathise with Matthew Dickie’s “dismay combined with a sense of foreboding”[50] upon encountering yet another attempt to define magic. The literature can be quite overwhelming, not least because within anthropology, the field in which most contemporary thinking on the subject of magic has taken place, magic has been “at its epistemological centre”[51] since its inception, and continues to generate extensive debate.[52]
There are well-known strengths and weaknesses to the different kinds of definition of magic that have been proffered,[53] however we categorise these, whether the definitions could be said, for example, to be essentialist,[54] functionalist,[55] locative-relational,[56] evolutionary,[57] developmental,[58] intellectualist,[59] instrumentalist,[60] linguistic,[61] performative,[62] emotionalist,[63] existential,[64] phenomenological,[65] mythopoetic,[66] or sensory.[67] For example, essentialist or substantivist definitions of magic have proved notoriously problematic. “Magic” and “religion” cannot be easily distinguished by differences between them in, for instance, intention, attitude, action, or social and moral evaluation,[68] nor even, as Jonathan Z. Smith has suggested, scale;[69] no criterion is effective in making a clear distinction between the two.[70] Functionalist definitions of magic suffer from the failing common to functionalist definitions more generally: they tend, in practice, to be dependent upon an implicit, substantive definition of something to which a function is ascribed.[71] They are also often procrustean, indeed many radically so, only capturing one aspect of a phenomenon in their definition, effectively amputating a great deal that is vital, and sacrificing “historical context in favor of taxonomic purity”.[72] For example, it seems unlikely that magic should be viewed solely as a response to risk, something that is found wherever there is “a hiatus in knowledge or practical control”, as Bronislaw Malinowski maintained.[73] Such an understanding is impossible to square with ethnographic data[74] and does not do justice to the range of motivations, emotions and practices most cultures associate with magic. Those who have argued that magic is a locative or relational category, something that, for example, distinguishes between those labelling and those labelled,[75] to designate a form of deviance against which a dominant discourse defines itself,[76] have to deal with the problem that such definitions are, at best, once again, only partial. The association of magic with specific subjects, places, practices and practitioners (some of whom may even self-identify as magicians) indicate that there is more to magic than just a way of creating and condemning alterity.[77] Within some cultures, including those in antiquity, magic clearly has an identifiable, agreed — if contestable — existence; it had a presence that was more tangible than mere rhetoric,[78] and was not necessarily understood in relation to central, sanctioned and normative forms of religious life and practice.[79] And considerably more could, of course, be said.
The business of definition has not been helped by the inconsistency of some major contributors within the field. For example, as Ronald Hutton has noted, although Dickie eschews essentialist definitions of magic in his comprehensive and influential Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, by the final third of his work he regularly uses the term in just such a manner.[80] It has also not helped that some major theorists, such as Max Weber, though they regularly discussed magic, and had a substantial impact on subsequent definitional debates, never themselves attempted to define it.[81]
Given the failure of scholarship to arrive at an agreed definition, Alfred Radcliffe-Brown famously suggested that there should be a moratorium on the use of the term “magic”.[82] However, this is not a way out of the impasse. In practice, it has just resulted in a proliferation of unhelpful circumlocutions, or forced and ungainly synonyms. For example, some scholars of religion in antiquity refer to magic as “ritual power”,[83] a designation that fails to take seriously non-ritual aspects of the phenomenon they are attempting to study. It precludes, for instance, analysis of the evil eye which could be cast inadvertently without any recourse to ritual.[84] Where magic can reasonably be argued to be a native category, as is the case in the early Roman empire, such circumlocutions tend to obfuscate and hamper rather than aid analysis.
Rodney Stark is right to observe that, generally speaking, “the term magic has been a conceptual mess”,[85] and this is especially true amongst those concerned with the study of magic in antiquity. Even though we have near universal belief in its significance, we do not have anything approaching a consensus about what it is or how it should be studied; instead we have “a confusing spectrum of divergent theories”.[86] Indeed, recent debates amongst those who study magic in the ancient Mediterranean have “trodden what appeared to be a reasonable amount of scholarly common ground into a quagmire”.[87] However, things are not as intractable as they might appear. A definition of “magic”, for our purposes, need not be one that is ahistorical nor universally applicable. Though such definitions can be useful to “think with”, or said to be sensitising[88] — that is, they can assist us in scrutinising the phenomenon more carefully by helping us to ask questions about both the subject and our own analysis of it — they can also be misleading and are unnecessary for interpreting imperial culture. All we require is a definition that fits this particular context. It does not need to extend to making some kind of sense of the world of the Azande, Trobriand Islanders or practitioners of contemporary Wicca.
However, deriving a definition that is rooted in first-century conceptualisations of magic is still a challenging task. Perhaps surprisingly, given that it carried a capital penalty,[89] “the Romans produced no precise definition of what magic was and what was not”.[90] Indeed, Apuleius raised the matter of definition when defending himself against the charge of witchcraft (an occasion when it was clearly of some consequence), asking a deceptively simple but devastating question of the lawyers representing his accuser: “I should therefore like to ask his most learned advocates how, precisely, they would define a magician?”[91]
Whatever definition we arrive at will, clearly, have its limitations, particularly given the range of different ethnic and regional cultures encompassed by the empire. Nonetheless, a definition derived from those things which can reasonably be assumed to have been considered magical by most people in the early Roman empire, largely, but not solely, indicated by the presence of a cluster of key Latin and Greek terms related to magical practitioners (Latin: magus, lamia, saga, maleficus, praecantrix, veneficus; Greek: μάγος, γόης, φάρμακος) and the practice of magic itself (Latin: magica, veneficia; Greek: μαγεία, γοητεία, φαρμακαεία), seems reasonable, even if, as the famous trial of Apuleius indicates, the meaning of such terms was both malleable and contestable.[92] Such a definition could, in Ogden’s taxonomy, be termed “linguistic”.[93]
However, I would also like to propose a definition that is polythetic,[94] to borrow a concept from a form of classification employed in biology, but also familiar in the study of religion in general as well as the study of religion in antiquity.[95] Such a form of definition allows it to reflect the multivalent interpretations of magic in the early Roman empire. That is, the definition that follows is based upon a set of characteristic properties regarded as indicative of magic, many of which need to be present for us to identify its presence in our sources (and then undertake the business of gauging its saliency), though none of which is either sufficient or necessary. It is useful to think of those things that were identified as magic in antiquity as possessing what Ludwig Wittgenstein referred to as a “family resemblance”, something that allows considerable variety whilst also allowing for identifiable commonality.[96] The definition I would like to use is also one that is dependent, as far as it is possible, upon the emic perspective of inhabitants of the first century,[97] or better, given disagreements and differences over what exactly merited the label “magic”, as we can see in Apuleius’ trial, emic perspectives of inhabitants of the early Roman empire.[98]
So, in brief, I believe it is both useful and legitimate to think of magic in the early Roman empire as something associated with characteristic:
(a) Practices. Magic was often thought to involve nocturnal and secret rites,[99] the use of incantations, spells and voces magicae,[100] as well as abnormal sacrifices, including the sacrifice of humans.[101]
(b) Practitioners. Although non-specialists could carry out magical acts,[102] a range of identifiable experts were associated with the practice of magic, from sorcerers and magicians to witches and root-cutters.[103]
(c) Places. Particular locations, especially those places connected with the dead and death, such as cemeteries, battlefields or places of execution,[104] and places that were secret or isolated, such as caves, ruins, or woods,[105] were regularly associated with magic.
(d) Times. Magic was especially associated with the night,[106] a full moon[107] or an eclipse.[108]
(e) Materials and artefacts. Specific plants and gemstones, as well as animal and human body parts, were thought to be necessary for the practice of magic.[109] Certain objects, such as amulets, magical books, voodoo dolls, lamellae and defixiones, and knotted threads,[110] were believed to be tools employed by those utilising it.
(f) Knowledge. Magic was usually thought to involve the possession and application of distinctive, specialist and secret knowledge. This could be of both a technical and propositional kind. In the case of the former, it could include such things as knowledge of specific rituals and practices, and, in the case of the latter, such things as knowledge of supernatural realms and their inhabitants, or the true natures of, and potential causal relationships between, animate and inanimate objects.[111]
(g) Gods and spirits. Magic was particularly associated with infernal, chthonic gods of the underworld, especially Hecate,[112] and the spirits of the dead, especially the restless dead, those who had died too early, or too violently or who had not received the appropriate burial rites, or had been killed by magical practitioners themselves.[113]
(h) Effects. Magic was usually thought to be something that was harmful to at least one of the parties involved.[114]
There are other traits that regularly appear in depictions of magic that were prominent in the early Roman empire.[115] Magic was, for example, regularly associated with particular geographical locations, such as Babylonia,[116] Egypt[117] or Thessaly,[118] and cities such as Ephesus[119] and Memphis,[120] or ethnic groups, both real and imagined, such as Chaldeans,[121] Hyperboreans,[122] Persians,[123] Egyptians,[124] Jews,[125] and the Marsi.[126] It was also usually deployed in specific agonistic contexts where the practitioner or client often had much to lose or gain, such as trade, law, sport and love.[127] It was sometimes spoken about in terms of compulsion, with the magician assumed to have the power to be able to compel even a god to act against their will.[128] However, the key characteristics I have just adumbrated are a useful distillation of the central features of magic in the early Roman empire, at least for most of its inhabitants (there were, of course, variations within some groups, notably Jews, and later Christians, who, in addition to sharing many of these general notions about magic, tended to equate the religious practices of others with magic).[129]
So, using our definition, perhaps unsurprisingly, the famous depiction of the witch Pamphile in Apulieus’ Metamorphoses could be said to contain (a) Practices, (b) Practitioners, (d) Times, and (e) Materials and Artefacts, that to inhabitants of the early Roman empire were characteristic of magic:
As night began … she arranged her deadly laboratory with its customary apparatus, setting out spices of all sorts, unintelligibly lettered metal plaques, the surviving remains of ill-omened birds, and numerous pieces of mourned and even buried corpses: here noses and fingers, there flesh-covered spikes from crucified bodies, elsewhere the preserved gore of murder victims and mutilated skulls wrenched from the teeth of wild beasts. Then she recited a charm over some pulsating entrails and made offerings with various liquids …. Next she bound and knotted those hairs together in interlocking braids and put them to burn on live coals along with several kinds of incense.[130]
Similarly, the description of events surrounding the death of Germanicus, as recounted by Tacitus, has (a) Practices, (c) Places, (e) Materials and Artefacts, (g) Gods and spirits, and (h) Effects, associated with magic by most in Graeco-Roman culture:
Explorations in the floor and walls [of the building in which Germanicus died] brought to light the remains of human bodies, spells, curses, leaden tablets engraved with the name Germanicus, charred and blood-smeared ashes, and others of the implements by which it is believed the living soul can be devoted to the powers of the infernal deities.[131]
However, using our definition, the much-discussed Isis theophany that is central to the climax of Apuleius’ Metamorphoses[132] and which leads to the protagonist’s return to human form, would not be considered an example of “magic” because it fails to possess any of its possible characteristics (other than it taking place at full moon, a time which, in any case, had specific non-magical associations for worshippers of Isis).[133] Whilst modern commentators, such as Stavros Frangoulidis, are entitled to label it magical,[134] depending upon what kind of definition of magic they are employing,[135] such a designation would have made little sense to its original readers.
Certainly, if we look at the implied definition of magic found in Roman legislation, our operational, polythetic definition appears congruent with what is assumed there. Sulla’s Lex Cornelia de sicariis et veneficiis of 81 BCE, the chief law relating to magic that was in force in the early Roman empire,[136] contains all of the elements of our definition (with the exception of a clear reference to characteristic (b) Place). Although we do not have the text of the Lex Cornelia de sicariis et veneficiis itself, this can be seen in excerpts from Pseudo-Paulus’ famous commentary on this law:
15. Those who perform, or arrange for the performance of, impious or nocturnal rites, in order to enchant, transfix, or bind someone, shall either be crucified or thrown to the beasts.
16. Those who sacrifice a man or obtain omens from his blood, or pollute a shrine or a temple, shall be thrown to the beasts or, if honestiores,[137] be punished capitally.
17. It is agreed that those guilty of the magic art be inflicted with the supreme punishment, i.e., be thrown to the beasts or crucified. Actual magicians, however, shall be burned alive.
18. No one is permitted to have in their possession books of the magic art; anyone in whose possession they are found shall have their property confiscated, and the books publicly burnt, and they themselves shall be deported to an island; humiliores shall be punished capitally. Not only is the profession of this art but also the knowledge prohibited.[138]
Of course, there was another side to magic in the Roman empire to that which we have discussed so far. For some, there was a respectable and venerable form of magic. So Apuleius, for example, initially defended himself against the accusation of sorcery by confirming that he was happy to be called a magus — as long as it was understood that by this he meant someone in the line of the ancient Persian magi,[139] priests of Zoroaster who were considered especially skilled in such things as oneirology, astrology, and additional forms of divination, including the ability to undertake otherworldly journeys.[140] And this was clearly distinguishable from the corrupt form that was popularly thought to be “magic”. As Calasiris, an Egyptian priest in Heliodorus’ Aethiopica declared:
Of our wisdom there is one kind that is common and — as I may term it — creeps on the ground, which is concerned with ghosts and occupied about dead bodies, using herbs and addicted to enchantments, neither tending itself nor bringing such as use it to any good end …. The other, my son, which is the true wisdom, from whence the counterfeit has degenerated.[141]
In the light of such material it might appear useful to speak of a variety of magics co-existing in the Roman empire, as Richard Gordon has suggested.[142] Indeed, forms of magic developed and changed over the centuries, and it is possible to see the increasing elaboration of practice from relatively simple Greek techniques of the classical period to the involved esoteric forms that are more common in the empire (evidenced in the increasing complexity of curse tablets and the growing popularity of a new genre of physica, works such as that of Cyranides that detail the occult forces of nature).[143] If we accept Fritz Graf’s analysis, we can see a shift from an essentially instrumental interest in magic to an epistemological fascination with what knowledge it might be able to provide about the supreme God. The latter was especially manifest in the various Hermetica that flourished from the mid-second century CE[144] and the theurgy of the Iamblichus that became prominent in the third,[145] though it might also have been present in the possible neo-Pythagorean revival associated with Nigidius Figulus which appeared in the late Republic.[146] However, whilst it is certainly important to note rarefied discourses of magic, and, indeed, different regional and ethnic traditions and emphases, this should not preclude us from identifying and scrutinising the significance of what most people judged to be magic, of making judgements on the saliency of something that constituted the generally held, shared culture of the empire. Our definition is one that reflects the dominant and most widespread understanding of magic in the early Roman empire, the kind that Calasiris calls “common”; a kind of magic identified by most commentators as taking a surprisingly similar form across the empire by at least the second century CE,[147] though present in most forms of Graeco-Roman culture sometime before that.
Just an illusion? Evaluating evidence for the presence of magic
Before we evaluate the evidence for magic in the early Roman empire, we need to begin by abandoning the fundamental assumption of many working in the field, or dependent upon work in this field, that magic must, of necessity, have been significant because the Roman empire was a pre-modern culture. In approaching the empire and its inhabitants we need to do something analogous to that which Mary Douglas, some decades ago, advocated anthropologists should do, and “ditch the myth of the pious primitive”.[148] We need to be aware that the salience of magic needs to be proven rather than assumed, however much some may have invested in the subject. Magic was not necessarily a constant or significant feature of all pre-modern societies, and we should not presume that it must have been for the inhabitants of the early Roman empire.[149]
Indeed, when we look at the evidence rather more closely, some perplexing things emerge and reasons for believing that magic was a significant element of early imperial culture and the day-to-day lives of its inhabitants appear less compelling. For example, the interest in magic in literary sources is a far from unproblematic indication of its saliency. Despite its centrality, Homer’s representation of magic is actually somewhat ambivalent and cannot be presumed to have contributed to its alleged importance in the empire. As well as providing the paradigmatic literary representations of magic, in the depiction of figures such as Circe[150] and Calypso,[151] Homer was also capable of demonstrating a sustained disinterest in it,[152] something that did not escape the attention of his readers: whilst the Odyssey is replete with references to magic,[153] there is, as Pliny the Elder observed, no mention of it at all in the Iliad.[154] The engaging depictions of magic by the likes of Apuleius, Lucian and Petronius,[155] with their accounts of such things as haunted houses and human sacrifice, are heavily stylised and formulaic and, as Graham Anderson has argued, reminiscent of folktales or better fairytales that predate these texts.[156] Such works tell us that stories about magic were considered entertaining and had an audience, but little else. Magic might “matter” but not in the sense that is usually assumed: the inhabitants of the early Roman empire could well be like the Dani of Papua New Guinea who show “more fear of ghosts in stories than they do in their everyday activities.”[157]
The reservations we have about the value of literary works as evidence for the widespread significance of magic in the early Roman empire should also extend to legal sources too. The existence of laws aimed specifically against magical practices and practitioners, such as the Lex Cornelia de sicariis et veneficiis, do not, in themselves, tell us much about the saliency of magic in the empire. Such laws do not necessarily reflect the sustained assumptions and anxieties of the wider cultures within which they operate. Indeed, laws against magic are often the residue of short-lived moral panics.[158] In this sense, laws like the Lex Cornelia de sicariis et veneficiis (and the earlier laws from which it was constituted),[159] may well be similar to such things as the Garrotter’s Act of 1863, which remained on the statute books in England and Wales for almost a century, and was a legal response to the sudden appearance of foreign stranglers who, albeit briefly, gripped the imagination though not the throats, of Victorian Londoners.[160]
Indeed, the limited number of prosecutions for witchcraft in the early Roman empire supports such an interpretation of the nature of such legislation and, in itself, is indicative of a general lack of interest in magic. Few people were tried and even less executed for magic in the empire (nor is there evidence of the extra-judicial or de facto killing of magical practitioners). Relative to the population of the empire as a whole, the numbers put to death appear to have been extremely small, and when judged against practices in other cultures, strikingly so. For example, although the data is not entirely unproblematic and cross-cultural comparisons can be invidious, the number of witches executed in only two years in the English region of East Anglia between 1645 and 1647 appears to be roughly comparable to the total number executed in the first few centuries of the Roman empire[161] — and the former had a population of less than one per cent of the latter.[162]
There is also a famous paradox, well known in antiquity, evident in the actions of those that did bring prosecutions against magical practitioners, which makes it difficult to believe that they really credited magic with the kind of power that is often assumed: as Apollonius of Tyana allegedly remarked, “If you think me a sorcerer, how will you chain me? And if you chain me, how will you think me a sorcerer?”[163] Indeed, not only would it be impossible to punish someone who had such power but, as Apuleius pointed out in his own defence, it would also be suicidal: “the man who believes in the truth of such a charge as this is certainly the last person in the world who should bring such an accusation.”[164]
The material culture associated with magic which can be dated to the early Roman empire is also a far from reliable indicator of the ubiquity of assumptions about its efficacy even though it is tempting to interpret such evidence in this way.[165] Of course, many artefacts associated with magic are, by their nature, ephemeral and unlikely to leave much of an impression on the archaeological record — one thinks, for example, of the magical threads that were used as charms or to effect binding spells[166]— but magical artefacts, or references to them, are surprisingly thin on the ground. For example, no objects that Romans would have considered unequivocally magical were discovered at Pompeii or Herculaneum,[167] and references to magic do not appear, even obliquely, in the abundant graffiti from these sites, material that allows “an attempt to define a popular culture of the time”.[168] As Andrew Wilburn has observed in his study of the archaeology of magic in Roman Egypt, Cyprus and Spain (a study predicated upon a much more expansive definition of magic than the one employed in this paper):[169]
The preserved evidence of enacted magic such as curse tablets is comparatively small when juxtaposed with other corpora of textual artifacts such as public inscriptions and ostraca. The number of published curse tablets stands at approximately 1,600 which derive from over a period of approximately one thousand years and the full geographic extent of the Roman Empire. In contrast, over one thousand ostraca have been published from the University of Michigan excavations at the site of Karnis alone.[170]
Even when we do discover objects that can, with reasonable certainty, be categorised as magical, what we can deduce from them about the significance of magic in the early Roman empire is far from self-evident. Although it is common to see such things as having “attendant beliefs and assumptions”[171] what exactly these might be is not easily discerned. What can we say about the “attendant beliefs and assumptions” possessed by an amulet that was claimed to render the wearer invisible?[172] Did those manufacturing and using such an object really think that it worked? Did they imagine it was as efficacious as, say, those amulets that were declared, rather more modestly, to relieve indigestion or alleviate a hangover? Or to make the wearer more popular or lucky? (all claims that allowed a rather more subjective assessment of their veracity).[173] What can we say about the kind of beliefs that “attended” to the defixio found in Hadrumetum (Sousse) in which a man sought to make four women fall in love with him? Does the large number of potential lovers tell us merely about the ambition of the man or does it tell us that he did not hold out much hope of the likely efficacy of such a practice in relation to any of the women named?[174] And what of a bracelet made up of over forty different “charms” found at Herculaneum?[175] Should it be considered evidence of the significance of magic in the life of the wearer? Or was it primarily decorative, sentimental, or even a form of mnemonic device, providing a means of exercising control over the universe, in a limited but effective way, though not through the supernatural power of magic but through the process of collecting to which it bears witness[176] and the autobiographical structuring of memory such an activity can facilitate?[177] Of course, none of these alternatives need be the sole “meaning” of the charm bracelet for the wearer or others creating or encountering it, and none need preclude the possibility that magic was, indeed, a constituent part of its variegated “attendant beliefs” but they do alert us to the possibility that magic might, at best, be just one, perhaps inconsequential element in the meaning ascribed to an object, even an object that some might assume must be understood in such a way.
Indeed, we should be careful not to mistake the presence of an object with the simple presence of particular ideas, magical or otherwise. Although artefacts may have the capacity to “symbolise the deepest human anxieties and aspirations”,[178] such as those associated with the agonistic obsessions of love, sport, law and business, that are, for example, the stuff of ancient magic, and such objects might relay “a cultural image of the way in which the universe works”,[179] they also have “social lives”[180] and “biographies”,[181] determined locatively and temporally, and we should not overlook what Woodward calls the “idiosyncrasies, incoherencies and sheer mundanity of the user’s perspective.”[182] We know, for example, that some who wore amulets (which were, as we have noted, not necessarily understood to be magical), had little interest in their supposed effects,[183] and others recommended their use for psychological benefits but completely disavowed any “worldview” implicit in their manufacture.[184]
Even tombstones do not provide us with evidence of the saliency of magic in the everyday lives of inhabitants of the Roman empire that is quite as solid as it might at first appear. We have tens of thousands of epitaphs, often recounting the manner in which the person commemorated met their death, but the epitaph mentioned at the outset of this paper is one of only a handful that speak of someone being killed by witchcraft.[185]
In short, the data often taken as evidence for the cultural significance of magic in the early Roman empire, even when examined on its own, in isolation from the wider social context to which we shall now turn, is not as unequivocal or necessarily as substantive as is often assumed.[186]
An empty box? The absence of magic
Although it is generally correct to say that absence of evidence is not evidence of absence, if magic were something of significance in the early Roman empire, we would expect to find evidence of its presence in sources that shed light on the day-to-day lives of its inhabitants,[187] that is, to find evidence of it in those texts and artefacts which, however imperfectly, could be said to be indicative of popular culture. If we leave aside those sources that are directly concerned with magic, such as the Papyri Graecae Magicae or Apuleius’ Apologia — compelling though they may be, and particularly so when grouped together in collections dedicated solely to the subject of magic in antiquity[188] — and instead look at those sources that reveal the general preoccupations of the time, we discover a near silence concerning all things magical. The lack of interest is striking and unequivocal. Witches, sorcerers, and spells warrant virtually no mention or none at all in, for example, the popular ethical literature common in the early Roman empire, the collections of proverbs, fables, gnomai, and exempla.[189] The only appearance of a magical practitioner in Aesop’s Fabulae, for example, a body of literature that was culturally omnipresent and popular across all strata of Graeco-Roman culture,[190] is one in which the powers of a witch are ridiculed (with no untoward effects):
One of the spectators, seeing her [a witch] being dragged out of the court said to her: “How is it that you claim to be able to avert the gods’ anger, that you were not even able to persuade human beings?”[191]
Nor is magic of consequence in the Vita Aesopi either, the comic biography of the fabulist, composed around the second century CE.[192] The collection of exempla by Valerius Maximus, from the reign of Tiberius, and a useful window into common assumptions and obsessions, likewise, contains no clear reference to magic.[193]
Magic and magicians also play little part in popular paradoxographical literature of the period, such as Phlegon of Tralles’ de Mirabilis, texts that seem to have had a wide readership across social and cultural groups in the Principate.[194] Nor do they feature in Artemidorus’ Oneirocritica, a handbook of dream interpretations that provides an extremely valuable repository of the anxieties of the time and which has been likened to an ethnography of the second-century Mediterranean world.[195] Whilst the Oneirocritica indicates that those who lived in the early Roman empire were fearful of such things as disease[196] and poverty,[197] and dreamed of a host of subjects, from having sex with their mother,[198] to being crucified,[199] or getting dressed the wrong way in the morning,[200] they did not dream of magicians or spells. Nor, from the range of interpretations given, was magic one of the things that they believed that their dreams were really about.[201] Magic is also not a subject that appears in Roman joke books, such as the Philogelos, again a useful source for identifying the general preoccupations of the time and which, instead, finds humour in such perennial topics as sickness, sex and intellectuals’ lack of common sense.[202] And it is not a concern of the popular do-it-yourself oracle books such as the Lots of Astrampsychos.[203] Although this text does have an exotic quality to it — it took its name from a mythical Zoroastrian priest[204] — when we scrutinise the wide variety of questions that could be asked of the oracle (of which there were 92), and the answers given (of which there were 1030), it is clear that magic was of no consequence.[205] Other things preoccupy the text and, one assumes, those using it, such as employment, health, love, fertility, travel, business and death. Nor is magic amongst the causes of fortune and misfortune assumed. Similarly, the popular Homeromanteion, an oracle which consisted of 216 lines of Homer that provided possible answers to whatever questions were put to it, makes no direct reference to magic or witchcraft even though many of the excerpts from Homer were taken from the Odyssey, a text which, as we have noted, has a considerable interest in magical themes.[206] Such material appears to indicate that most people were unconcerned by magic, most of the time. They clearly did not think it had explanatory power in making sense of their lives or obtaining their goals. Nor was it something perceived to be a threat. Nor did they ascribe to it any symbolic significance. They were, it appears, at best, indifferent to it. From these popular cultural texts it is fair to conclude that it had little saliency in the early Roman empire.
In the light of the preceding discussion, it is apparent that Betz’s assertion that, “Magical beliefs and practices can hardly be overestimated in their importance for the daily lives of the people”,[207] is untenable. It is clear that the significance of magic in the lives of those in the early Roman empire can, in fact, all too easily be overestimated and, indeed, regularly is. To put it crudely, and I am aware the distinction has its limitations, for most of the inhabitants of the Roman empire, for most of the time, magic appears to have been largely the stuff of stories and not of life.
Explaining indifference
It is not necessary to explain why inhabitants of the early Roman empire had such limited interest in magic in order for our conclusions about its lack of saliency to stand. Nonetheless, given that it is often, even if erroneously, assumed that magic was a significant preoccupation of pre-modern cultures, this unusual finding does invite further comment and I would like to posit some tentative, partial, explanations for this phenomenon. Indifference is under theorised in the study of religion in antiquity (although it is of increasing interest for the study of contemporary religion)[208] nonetheless I would like to suggest three possible reasons for the absence of interest in magic in the lives of most inhabitants of the empire, most of the time. I believe that it is probably, in part, a consequence of the existence of widespread scepticism of two kinds, which whilst related are not synonymous: (a) scepticism concerning the supernatural and (b) scepticism concerning magic.[209] In addition, it is also likely to be (c) a function, on those limited occasions when it was indeed used, of the agonistic contexts within which magic was deployed in the early Roman empire, something that we shall return to at the conclusion of this essay.
It is important to emphasise that the term “scepticism” is used here both in the modern, popular sense of active disbelief, as well as the related sense of the necessary suspension of judgement where a valid conclusion is impossible, for example, about the causation of a phenomenon. I am not using it with Pyrrhonism and formal philosophical Scepticism in mind.[210] It is also important to emphasise that scepticism about magic does not necessarily imply scepticism about the power of the gods, although the reverse is not the case.[211]
However, the use of the concept “scepticism” requires some defence. It could be said to be misguided, to be both unhelpfully polarising[212] and to approach the subject with unwarranted, anachronistic, presuppositions about the necessary significance of “belief” in the study of religion generally, and the religions of antiquity more specifically.[213] As Ken Dowden quite rightly says:
One of the hardest features of ancient religion for the modern student is the sheer unimportance of belief. […] The ancient religions are not dead faiths, they are obsolete practices.[214]
It could also be said to be an idea that does not do justice to the mutually contradictory ways of talking about the gods that were common and allowable in the empire that resulted from “the different kinds of assent and criteria of judgement”[215] applied in different contexts; an approach to religion characterised by what Veyne calls “mental Balkanization”.[216] Such a view is most clearly evident in the three very different theologiae of poetry, politics and philosophy identified by Varro.[217]
Nonetheless, whilst it is true that public, elective, and domestic cults of the empire did not have any place for instrumental or soteriological conceptualisations of belief,[218] and nor did magic, religion and magic in the empire were both predicated on certain assumptions, such as the efficacy of ritual and the power of the gods that underpinned their workings.[219] Such “beliefs” (or, perhaps better, “ideas” or “convictions”) were not the kind that required active assent — they were not beliefs “in” but rather beliefs “that”[220] — they were not of a soteriological but of an epistemological kind.
However, even beliefs of this sort can be the subject of dissent (rituals, for example, can be left undone) and so it is not unreasonable to speculate on the role of scepticism in making sense of the lack of interest in magic in the empire. And whilst it is true that most of those in the empire operated with a number of different, apparently mutually contradictory, theologiae of the kind identified by Varro, this does not preclude us from talking about scepticism, although it does require us to be sensitive to the situational articulation of such beliefs so that we do not misread the evidence.
Sceptical attitudes towards the supernatural
There is evidence of a significant degree of scepticism concerning the supernatural in the early Roman empire, particularly in relation to the possibility of direct intervention by the gods or other supernatural powers in human life (something that is not necessarily the same as scepticism about the existence of the gods per se). Such an argument is not dependent upon the number of those who identified themselves with philosophical schools that were hostile to supernaturalism, such as the Epicureans, Cynics, and Sceptics, something that, relative to the population as a whole, is unlikely to have been large.[221] We should not overlook the attempts by members of these movements to disseminate key doctrines beyond their core adherents, seen, for example, in the remarkable inscription at Oenoanda in Lycia which gave passers-by access to an extensive collection of Epicurean treatises,[222] or the notorious behaviour of Cynics that was intended, in part, to both embody and communicate their ideas to a wide audience,[223] but their success appears to have been limited.[224]
Rather scepticism towards the supernatural went beyond such circles and was not necessarily associated with strong philosophical commitments or philosophical identities of any particular kind. This is evident, for example, in historiographical and medical discourses prominent in the early Roman empire in which the supernatural was not a causative agent in the lives of humans. Some historians of the period excoriated those that believed it was,[225] whilst most seem to have been studiously “ambivalent”[226] about the direct intervention of the gods in human history, and it is common to find naturalistic explanations for allegedly supernatural events,[227] even if many were not always consistent in their approach.[228] Naturalistic explanations of disease were also dominant in professional medical discourses of the empire that were indebted, directly or indirectly, to the Hippocratic tradition that effectively demythologised supernatural aetiologies.[229] Of course, such rational approaches to disease and healing should not be crudely contrasted with those that allowed room for intervention from the gods (even the physician Galen could believe that the god Asklepios had saved him from the plague and that he was only a doctor because the god had appeared in dreams to his father),[230] nor should we assume that they were dominant in popular culture[231] but they were well known[232] and contributed to the normalisation of discourse in imperial culture which was sceptical of the supernatural.[233]
Although no one in the Roman empire achieved the notoriety of the infamous “atheist” Diagoras of Melos of the fifth century BCE who not only mocked the Eleusinian mysteries but, after his prayer for the return of a lost manuscript went unanswered, boiled up some turnips on a fire kindled with a wooden statue of Heracles,[234] it is also the case that there were some who, at least on occasion, showed a comparable lack of concern for the supernatural power of the gods. The general Claudius Pulcher, for example, famously drowned the sacred chickens who refused to eat when offered grain, and so failed to provide a positive omen for his forthcoming (and unsuccessful) campaign, quipping “If they will not eat, let them drink.”[235] And he was hardly alone.[236] According to Suetonius, Roman crowds, grief-stricken at the death Germanicus despite their prayers, “stoned the temples, and toppled the divine altars, while others flung their household gods into the street”, in part, no doubt, in an attempt to punish the gods but also an indication that the gods were judged to be powerless.[237]
It was not unusual to doubt whether gods were capable of intervening in human affairs,[238] and such a position was not limited to moments of collective crisis or disappointment.[239] We find plenty of examples of popular, everyday scepticism in the period. So for example, one of Babrius’ Aesopic fables reads: “Since the gods do not know who steals from their own temples what is the use of appealing to them for help in finding any other lost property?”[240] In the Enchiridion, Epictetus is reported as observing that those who did not obtain what they expected in life were prone to abuse the gods and accuse them of being uninterested in human affairs, something that was particularly true of farmers, sailors, merchants and those who had been bereaved.[241]
On occasion, the gods, both new and old, could be the subjects of ruthless satire[242] and irreverent behaviour: their festivals[243] and oracles[244] mocked, their sacred groves cut down,[245] sacrifices stolen,[246] and cult images abused.[247] People could even dress up as gods for fancy dress parties[248] and make the condemned parade as gods for sport before their execution.[249] It is, perhaps, no surprise that there was such widespread concern in the empire about the danger of impietas (“denying the gods the honours and rank that were rightfully theirs”)[250] and, in particular, impietas that was deliberate, with malicious intent, rather than accidental (prudens dolo malo rather than imprudens), something that was inexpiable.[251] Clearly, there were at least some in the empire more than willing to behave in a manner that showed no fear of supernatural retribution, to the concern of their contemporaries.[252]
In addition to scepticism of the supernatural evident in the behaviour of some towards the gods, there are also indications that other supernatural powers could be approached with significant scepticism. Epitaphs, for example, could mock the existence of ghosts[253] and interest in demons could be ranked alongside interest in quail fighting, as a frivolous waste of time.[254] Even those traditionally believed, at least amongst the elite, Roman males who dominate our literary sources, to be particularly receptive to such beliefs, had, according to Cicero, albeit writing from the context of the late Republic, become more rational:
Who now credits that the hippocentaur or the Chimaera ever existed? Is there a single old woman to be found who is so unhinged as the be sorely afraid of those monsters in the nether world in which people once believed? Time obliterates the falsehoods of common belief.[255]
The existence of scepticism towards the supernatural in the early Roman empire, whether of an intellectual or apparently more visceral kind, is certainly not key, nor even, necessarily significant, in explaining the lack of saliency of magic, but it undoubtedly had a part to play in this phenomenon.
Sceptical attitudes towards magic
There is considerable evidence that magic in the early Roman empire was regularly denounced as fraudulent. As Gordon has effectively demonstrated, important representations of magic in antiquity “conceived of it not as powerful for harm but, on the contrary as vacant show, as empty nonsense.”[256] And such scepticism was not just an elite perspective: “Although this view is associated generally with the educated elite, it was also a view widespread in the population at large: for most of the time, under most circumstances, many people considered … it absurd”;[257] something that played on people’s foolish and extravagant hopes. Those writers, such as Petronius, that made extensive use of magic in their narratives did so “to enthral and entertain in their own right, but at the same time they serve to convey the gullibility and feeble-mindedness of their tellers”.[258] And they were not alone. The hostility towards magical practitioners evident in the Aesopic fable to which we earlier referred[259] is a sentiment that recurs elsewhere.[260] The failure of magic to achieve results was infamous. The inefficacy of love magic, for example, is a recurring topos in literature.[261] In Ovid’s Heroides even Medea has to admit she cannot be successful at this.[262] The idea that magicians and witches were frauds who prayed on the vulnerable is a recurring motif in a range of texts.[263] It can be seen, for example, in Tacitus’ account of the story of the young Servilia, tried before the Senate for using magicians to determine the future fate of her family after it had fallen foul of Nero, and forced to commit suicide as a consequence.[264]
Stinging criticisms of magical claims can be found in medical writing too. Galen mounted a savage attack on Pamphilius, composer of a treatise on herbs which included extensive discussion of their magical properties, denouncing it as “long-winded Egyptian sorcery” so incredible that not even a child could believe it.[265] And for the encyclopaedist Pliny the Elder the fact that Nero had reportedly sought to become a magician but, despite all the means he had at his disposal, had failed, was evidence that magic was fraudulent, “ineffectual, vain”.[266] Cynic criticisms of the claims of magicians were also common. According to Lucian, Demonax confronted a magician who claimed to be able to obtain whatever he wanted by means of incantations, and offered to go to the nearest baker and turn a coin into a loaf of bread.[267]
For some critics, magic was no more than trickery. For example, Plutarch mentions a witch using her knowledge of the occurrence of an eclipse to achieve the so-called Thessalian trick:[268]
Aglaonice, a Thessalonian woman — though being thoroughly acquainted with the periods of the full moon, when it is subject to eclipse, and knowing, beforehand the time what the moon was due to be overtaken by the earth’s shadow, imposed upon the (other) women, and made them all believe that she was drawing down the moon.[269]
Indeed, a number of authors appear to have written works containing rational, reductionist explanations of the secrets of magic. These evidently circulated widely in the empire as Philostratus can mention in passing that several individuals “who have laughed out loud at the art”, had written books on how its effects were manufactured, and seems to assume that these would be familiar to his readers.[270] Such rationalisations were of various kinds. Some seem surprisingly modern whilst others are wedded to specific ideas about causation that might seem implausible to us.[271] The plausibility of such rationalisations to us is, of course, of no consequence — the issue is the plausibility of such rationalisations for those who lived in the early Roman empire.
Although no texts of the kind alluded to by Philostratus have come down to us, Hippolytus’ Refutatio omnium haeresium[272] does include a substantial section that appears to be dependent upon a source of this kind, and gives us our most extensive exposé of the fraudulent techniques of magicians. In this we hear, for example, that magicians demonstrated their powers — such as drawing down the moon and reading sealed letters — in mostly darkened rooms, a context conducive to deception, and used such staples of modern stage magic as misdirection, prestidigitation, and ingenious stage props.[273] A skull could be made to speak, for example, by the surreptitious use of the long windpipe of a crane;[274] the clever deployment of rocks, planks and sheets of brass, could create the illusion that the magician is able to summon up thunder.[275]
Such books may well have made public the secrets of a particular genre known as Paignia or “trifles”, of which our most extensive, surviving fragment, ascribed to Democritus, can be found, somewhat tellingly, in the Papyri Graecae Magicae.[276] These works seem to have given specific recipes to create dramatic effects, akin to childhood chemistry experiments, some of which were designed to liven up dinner parties[277] but others of which, such as those found in the Paignia of Salpe, or the collection by Anaxilaus of Larissa, were evidently intended to be employed in other contexts,[278] and “could be used to impress the gullible with the superhuman powers of the magician”.[279]
Some provided rational explanations of the apparent effects of magic of a somewhat different kind. Rather than expose the techniques of its practitioners, they attacked the non-falsifiable nature of its claims. Such criticisms had a long pedigree. The author of the Hippocratic work, De morbo sacro, for example, said of magicians that if a patient recovered, they would claim the credit but if they died, they would “have a sure fund of excuses, with the defence that they are not at all to blame, but the gods.”[280]
And a similar argument is made by Philostratus who provides a surprisingly modern-sounding explanation for the apparent success of magic: to those committed to its use it can never fail, the believer will always provide technical or other excuses to justify whatever outcome occurs; an observation strikingly reminiscent of Malinowski.[281]
The vulnerability of magic to rational criticism in the early Roman empire is perhaps no better seen than, somewhat paradoxically, in the defence used by some of those tried for practising it. As Pliny recounts, a farmer accused of achieving outstanding yields by magical means defended himself by explaining that toil, not magic, led to his abundant harvests.[282] Scepticism about magic was clearly vibrant in the empire and may also have contributed to its lack of cultural saliency.
The deployment of magic
The lack of significance of magic in the day-to-day lives of inhabitants of the early Roman empire was probably not only a consequence of scepticism about the supernatural and scepticism about magic itself. It may also have been, in part, a consequence of the context of its deployment, on the limited occasions when some made use of it, something that, as we noted earlier, appears to have been primarily agonistic. There is good reason for thinking that such agonistic use accompanied conceptualisations of magic in which it would be understood to be insubstantial; something ephemeral, equivocal and transitory.
The approach taken by Galina Lindquist,[283] is particularly useful for identifying the nature of such magic. Magic accessed in contexts characterised by deep uncertainty and lack of control,[284] according to Lindquist, is a form of materialised “hope” conjured up by frustrated agency, “where the uncertainty of life calls for methods of existential reassurance and control that rational and technical means cannot offer.”[285] However, the use of magic is not just an attempt to stack the odds in one’s favour through supernatural assistance but has other, more substantive effects. For example, Lindquist usefully suggests that it can redefine a situation, taking away responsibility and accountability for misfortune by transforming “risk” (something dependent upon the decision of an individual) into “danger” (something that can be attributed to the environment).[286] As she puts it, “When one risks and loses, one has only oneself to blame. In danger, if one is struck and hit, one is an unwitting victim, unfortunate but not guilty.”[287] There is a temporal and contingent dimension to belief of this kind, and it is not useful to think only in terms of what someone “believes” when a curse is written or spell cast but also about the subsequent form this takes (as Jean-Claude Schmitt has rightly said, “a belief is never a completed activity”).[288] Once the challenge has passed, Lindquist found that the need for magic or even the recognition of its efficacy often diminishes or vanishes.[289] Clients create post hoc rationalisations of events, similar to Arthur Kleinman’s “explanatory models” familiar from medical anthropology and which reflect the plural, indeterminate, and mutable character of potential interpretations over time.[290] Although we lack first-hand accounts to confirm this reading for the early Roman empire, I would suggest that narrations of magic in this period, for most of the limited numbers that seem to have accessed it, would have taken a similar shape to that found in the lives of Lindquist’s contemporary informants: it would acquire a degree of potential saliency at time of need but rather less or none in retrospect as the individual returns to a society in which magic, when it was thought about at all, was viewed as an unsanctioned and problematic activity — whether because it was something shocking and subversive or something embarrassing and risible.
Conclusion
There is a great deal more that can be said about the nature and place of magic in the early Roman empire. It would, for example, be useful to explain why magic did have considerable and unusual saliency for the early Christians, and the factors that led them to conjure up a useful, oppositional illusion of an enchanted and enslaved world.[291] The alleged significance of magic in the empire is not solely a matter of smoke and mirrors, but by arriving at their estimations of its importance by focusing solely on evidence of its presence, of being too quick to fall under the spell of texts such as the Papyri Graecae Magicae, scholars in the field could be said to have unwittingly been guilty of the classic magician’s trick of misdirection, and have themselves missed perhaps the feature of magic in the early Roman empire that is its most surprising: its lack of significance in the day-to-day lives of its inhabitants. Whilst they clearly enjoyed stories about magic, magic itself seems to have been largely inconsequential and ephemeral, of only fleeting importance, and the subject of the most attenuated and sporadic interest except amongst a handful. We have made some suggestions as to why this might be so, but the necessary process of revision and re-description has only just begun. Despite the plethora of publications in the field, substantial work, some of the most fundamental kind, clearly remains to be done.
- For example, Hans Dieter Betz, ed., The Greek Magical Papyri in Translation, Including the Demotic Spells, 2nd ed. (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992), xli. ↵
- Pliny, Naturalis historia 28.4.19. Pliny also claimed that such belief was not new but had "held sway throughout the world for many ages" (30.1.1). ↵
- Philostratus, Vita Apollonii 8.1–31. For Apollonius and the accusation of magic, see Roshan J. Abraham, “Magic and Religious Authority in Philostratus’ ‘Life of Apollonius of Tyana’” (PhD thesis, University of Pennsylvania, 2009); Erkki Koskenniemi, Apollonios von Tyana in der neutestamentlichen Exegese : Forschungsbericht und Weiterführung der Diskussion, WUNT 61 (Tübingen: Mohr, 1994); Andy M. Reimer, Miracle and Magic: A Study in the Acts of the Apostles and the Life of Apollonius of Tyana, JSNTSup 235 (London: Sheffield Academic Press, 2002). ↵
- Apuleius, Apologia (Pro se de magia). For studies of the Apologia, see Adam Abt, Die Apologie des Apuleius von Madaura und die antike Zauberei: Beiträge zur Erläuterung, der schrift de magia, Religionsgeschichtliche Versuche und Vorarbeiten 4.2. (Giessen: Töopelmann, 1908), 39–86; Keith R. Bradley, “Law, Magic, and Culture in the ‘Apologia’ of Apuleius,” Phoenix 51.2 (1997): 203–23, https://doi.org/10.2307/1088495; Fritz Graf, Magic in the Ancient World, trans. Franklin Philip, Revealing Antiquity 10 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997), 65–88; Stephen J. Harrison, Apuleius: A Latin Sophist (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 39–86; Vincent Hunink, ed., “Pro Se de Magia: (Apologia). Text and Commentary” (Amsterdam: J. C. Gieben, 1997); Ulrike Riemer, “Fascinating but Forbidden? Magic in Rome,” in A Kind of Magic: Understanding Magic in the New Testament and Its Religious Environment, ed. Michael Labahn and L. J. Lietaert Peerbolte, LNTS 306 (London: T. &T. Clark, 2007), 160–72; Werner Riess, ed., Paideia at Play: Learning and Wit in Apuleius (Groningen: Barkhuis, 2008); James B. Rives, “Magic in Roman Law: The Reconstruction of a Crime,” Classical Antiquity 22.2 (2003): 313–39, https://doi.org/10.1525/ca.2003.22.2.313. Apollonius and Apuleius are also both discussed by Augustine. See Fritz Graf, “Augustine and Magic,” in The Metamorphosis of Magic from Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period, ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra, Groningen Studies in Cultural Change 1 (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), 87–103. ↵
- Tacitus, Annales 2.69. See also Suetonius, Gaius Caligula 3.3 and Dio Cassius 57.18.9. See Allan A. Lund, “Zur Vergiftung des Germanicus (Tac. Ann. 2, 69),” Philologus 153.1 (2009): 173–80, https://doi.org/10.1524/phil.2009.0011; Anne-Marie Tupet, “Les pratiques magiques à la mort de Germanicus,” in Mélanges de littérature et d’épigraphie latines, d’histoire ancienne et d’archéologie. Hommage à la mémoire de Pierre Wuillemier, ed. H. Le Bonniec and G. Vallet (Paris: Gallimard, 1980), 345–52. Germanicus died in Antioch-on-the-Orontes in 19 CE. ↵
- Petronius' Satyricon could also be legitimately classified as a novel, despite the extensive use of poetry. However, substantial sections of this work are missing. We only have books fourteen, fifteen, and sixteen out of the twenty-four books that probably constituted the original. See Gareth Schmeling, A Commentary on the Satyrica of Petronius (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 460–61. The Satyricon also shows an extensive interest in magic. See, for example, Petronius, Sat. 61–63, 131. ↵
- For studies of the representation of magic in the Metamorphoses, see Stavros Frangoulidis, Witches, Isis and Narrative: Approaches to Magic in Apuleius’ “Metamorphoses” (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2008); Luca Graverini, Literature and Identity in the Golden Ass of Apuleius, trans. Benjamin Todd Lee (Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press, 2012); David Walter Leinweber, “Witchcraft and Lamiae in ‘The Golden Ass,’” Folklore 105 (1994): 77–82, https://doi.org/10.2307/1260631; Consuelo Ruiz-Montero, “Magic in the Ancient Novel,” in The Greek and the Roman Novel: Parallel Readings, ed. Michael Paschalis et al. (Groningen: Barkhuis, 2007), 38–56; John J. Winkler, Auctor and Actor: A Narratological Reading of Apuleius’s the Golden Ass (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1985). Apuleius' novel has had a considerable effect on the subsequent portrayals of magic and witchcraft in Europe; see Julia Haig Gaisser, The Fortunes of Apuleius and the “Golden Ass”: A Study in Transmission and Reception (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008). A Greek version of the same story, Pseudo-Lucian's Onos, displays a similar interest in magic. For the Onos, see Graham Anderson, Studies in Lucian’s Comic Fiction (Leiden: Brill, 1976), 34–67 — although Anderson argues for Lucian's authorship. Both the Metamorphoses and the Onos were based on an earlier, longer, Greek version of the story; see H. J. Mason, “Greek and Latin Versions of the Ass-Story,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. II.34.2., ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1994), 1665–1707; Helmut van Thiel, Der Eselsroman, 2 vols., Zetemata: Monographien zur klassischen Altertumswissenschaft 54.1 (München: C. H. Beck, 1971). ↵
- For treatments of magic and magical practitioners in classical literature see, for example, Samuel Eitrem, “La magie comme motif littéraire chez les grecs et les Romains,” Symbolae Osloenses 21.1 (1941): 39–83, https://doi.org/10.1080/00397674108590361; J. E Lowe, Magic in Greek and Latin Literature (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1929); Georg Luck, “Witches and Sorcerers in Classical Literature,” in Witchcraft and Magic in Europe: Ancient Greece and Rome, ed. Bengt Ankarloo and Stuart Clark, Athlone History of Witchcraft and Magic in Europe 2 (London: Athlone, 1999), 91–158; Elizabeth Ann Pollard, “Witch-Crafting in Roman Literature and Art: New Thoughts on an Old Image,” Magic, Ritual, and Witchcraft 3.2 (2008): 119–55, https://doi.org/10.1353/mrw.0.0115; Kimberly B. Stratton, Naming the Witch: Magic, Ideology, and Stereotype in the Ancient World (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 2007); Anne-Marie Tupet, La Magie dans la poésie latine (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1976). ↵
- See Heraclitus, Allegoriae Homericae 1.5-6; cf. 76.3–5; Horace, Epistulae 2.2.41–2; Quintilian, Institutio oratoria 1.8.5. For the place of Homer in both Greek and Roman education, see Stanley Frederick Bonner, Education in Ancient Rome: From the Elder Cato to the Younger Pliny (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1977), 213; Henri Marrou, Histoire de l’education dans l’antiquité, 6th ed. (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1965), 246–47; Teresa Morgan, Literate Education in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 69–71, 105–15. See also Petronius, Sat. 48, 59. For a discussion of the significance of Homer in Roman culture more generally, see Joseph Farrell, “Roman Homer,” in The Cambridge Companion to Homer, ed. Robert Fowler (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 254–71. ↵
- Pliny, Nat. 30.2.5. ↵
- For the Papyri Graecae Magicae, see Betz, The Greek Magical Papyri; William M. Brashear, “The Greek Magical Papyri,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. II.18.5, ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1995), 3380–3684; Karl Preisendanz, Adam Abt, and Albert Henrichs, eds., Papyri graecae magicae: die griechischen Zauberpapyri, 2nd ed. (Stuttgart: Teubner, 1973). ↵
- Maryse Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet: Magical Amulets in the First Book of Cyranides (Amsterdam: J. C. Gieben, 1987). ↵
- For the Testament of Solomon, see Gideon Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 179–82; Peter Busch, Das Testament Salomos: die älteste christliche Dämonologie, kommentiert und in deutscher Erstübersetzung, TUGAL 153 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2006); Dennis C. Duling, “The Testament of Solomon : Retrospect and Prospect,” Journal for the Study of the Pseudepigrapha 1.2 (1988): 87–112; Duling, “Testament of Solomon,” in The Old Testament Pseudepigrapha: Apocalyptic Literature and Testaments, ed. J. Charlesworth (New York, NY: Doubleday, 1983), 935–59; Sarah Iles Johnston, “The Testament of Solomon from Late Antiquity to the Renaissance,” in Metamorphosis of Magic from Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period, ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra, Groningen Studies in Cultural Change 1 (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), 35–49; Todd Klutz, Rewriting the Testament of Solomon: Tradition, Conflict and Identity in a Late Antique Pseudepigraphon, LSTS 53 (London: T&T Clark, 2005); Sarah L. Schwarz, “Reconsidering the Testament of Solomon,” Journal for the Study of the Pseudepigrapha 16.3 (2007): 203–37, https://doi.org/10.1177/0951820707077166. Magic can also be found in texts concerned with other things, such as the pharmacopeia of Dioscorides. Dioscorides distinguished the medical usage of plants from their alleged magical properties in his De materia medica, placing the latter at the end of each chapter. He also made it clear to the reader that such traditions consisted of what others had said, rather than what he himself had determined through his own experience, experiment and observation (Praef. 2–5). See, for example, De materia medica 1.90, 1.103, 2.104, 2.125, 2,126, 3.91, 3.131, 4.20, 4.76, 4.130. See John M. Riddle, Dioscorides on Pharmacy and Medicine (Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, 1985), 84. For a valuable translation and commentary, see Lily Y. Beck, trans., Pedanius Dioscorides of Anazarbus, de Materia Medica, Altertumswissenschaftliche Texte und Studien 38 (Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann, 2005). ↵
- For treatments of the theme of magic in Acts, see Susan R. Garrett, The Demise of the Devil: Magic and the Demonic in Luke’s Writings (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 1989); Hans Josef Klauck, Magic and Paganism in Early Christianity: The World of the Acts of the Apostles, trans. Brian McNeil (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 2000); Daniel Marguerat, “Magic and Miracle in the Acts of the Apostles,” in Magic in the Biblical World: From the Rod of Aaron to the Ring of Solomon, ed. Todd Klutz, JSNTSup 245 (London: T&T Clark, 2003), 100–124; Stanley E. Porter, “Magic in the Book of Acts,” in A Kind of Magic: Understanding Magic in the New Testament and Its Religious Environment, ed. Michael Labahn and L. J. Lietaert Peerbolte, LNTS 306 (London: T. & T. Clark, 2007), 107–21; Reimer, Miracle and Magic: A Study in the Acts of the Apostles and the Life of Apollonius of Tyana; Rainer Reuter, “Animosity against Jewish and Pagan Magic in the Acts of the Apostles,” in Animosity, the Bible, and Us, ed. John T. Fitzgerald, Fika van Rensberg, and Herrie F. van Roey (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2009), 123–36; Scott Shauf, Theology as History, History as Theology: Paul in Ephesus in Acts 19, BZNW 133 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2005). ↵
- See, for example, the magical battle between Peter and Simon Magus found in Acts of Peter 23–32. See Jan N. Bremmer, “Magic in the Apocryphal Acts of the Apostles,” in The Metamorphosis of Magic: From Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period, ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra, Groningen Studies in Cultural Change 1 (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), 51–70; Jan N. Bremmer, ed., The Apocryphal Acts of Peter: Magic, Miracles and Gnosticism, Studies on the Apocryphal Acts of the Apostles 3 (Leuven: Peeters, 1998); Wilhelm Schneemelcher, “The Acts of Peter,” in New Testament Apocrypha: Writings Related to the Apostles, Apocalypses and Related Subjects, ed. Wilhelm Schneemelcher, trans. Robert McLachlan Wilson, vol. 2 (Cambridge: James Clarke, 1992). ↵
- Notably Bar-Jesus (Acts 13.6–12) and Simon Magus (Acts of Peter 4–32). For studies of the conflict between Bar-Jesus and Paul, see Susan R. Garrett, “Light on a Dark Subject and Vice Versa: Magic and Magicians in the New Testament,” in Religion, Science, and Magic: In Concert and Conflict, ed. Jacob Neusner, Ernest S. Frerichs, and Paul Virgil McCracken Flesher (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 142–65; Garrett, The Demise of the Devil, 79–87; Arthur Darby Nock, “Paul and the Magus,” in Essays on Religion and the Ancient World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), 308–30; Rick Strelan, “Who Was Bar Jesus (Acts 13,6-12)?,” Biblica 85.1 (2004): 65–81. Simon is first mentioned in Acts 8.9–24 where he is rebuked for attempting to purchase the miraculous power of the Holy Spirit. He acquired the epithet "Magus" in subsequent literature and became a figure associated with both magic and gnosticism. See Tamás Adamik, “The Image of Simon Magus in the Christian Tradition,” in The Apocryphal Acts of Peter, ed. Jan N. Bremmer, Studies on the Apocryphal Acts of the Apostles 3 (Leuven: Peeters, 1998), 52–64; J. Duncan M. Derrett, “Simon Magus (Acts 8:9-24),” Zeitschrift für die neutestamentliche Wissenschaft und die Kunde der älteren Kirche 73.1 (1982): 52–68; M. J. Edwards, “Simon Magus, the Bad Samaritan,” in Portraits: Biographical Representation in the Greek and Latin Literature of the Roman Empire, ed. Catharine Edwards and S. Swaine (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 69–91; Alberto Ferreiro, “‘Simon Magus, Dogs, and Simon Peter,’” in Devil, Heresy and Witchcraft in the Middle Ages: Essays in Honor of Jeffrey B. Russell, ed. Alberto Ferreiro and Jeffrey Burton Russell (Leiden: Brill, 1998), 45–89; Alberto Ferreiro, Simon Magus in Patristic, Medieval and Early Modern Traditions, Studies in the Histories of Christian Traditions 125 (Leiden: Brill, 2005); Gerd Lüdemann, “The Acts of the Apostles and the Beginnings of Simonian Gnosis,” New Testament Studies 33.3 (1987): 420–26; Gerard P. Luttikhuizen, “Simon Magus as a Narrative Figure in the Acts of Peter,” in Apocryphal Acts of Peter, ed. Jan N. Bremmer, Studies on the Apocryphal Acts of the Apostles 3 (Leuven: Peeters, 1998), 39–51; Ayse Tuzlak, “The Magician and the Heretic: The Case of Simon Magus,” in Magic and Ritual in the Ancient World, ed. Paul A. Mirecki and Marvin Meyer, Religions in the Graeco-Roman World 141 (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 416–26. ↵
- Acts 19.11–20. For studies of this narrative, see Klauck, Magic and Paganism in Early Christianity, 97–101; Shauf, Theology as History, History as Theology: Paul in Ephesus in Acts 19; Garrett, The Demise of the Devil, 89–99; Rick Strelan, Strange Acts: Studies in the Cultural World of the Acts of the Apostles, BZNW 126 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2004), 107–12. For the symbolism of book burning in the empire, see Daniel Christopher Sarefield, “The Symbolics of Book Burning: The Establishment of a Christian Ritual of Persecution,” in The Early Christian Book, ed. William E. Klingshim and Linda Safran (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2007), 159–73; Daniel Christopher Sarefield, “Book Burning in the Christian Roman Empire: Transforming a Pagan Rite of Purification,” in Violence in Late Antiquity: Perceptions and Practices, ed. H. A. Drake (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006), 287–96. ↵
- See Christopher A. Faraone and Amina Kropp, “Inversion, Adversion and Perversion as Strategies in Latin Curse Tablets,” in Magical Practice in the Latin West: Papers from the International Conference Held at the University of Zaragoza 30 Sept-1 Oct 2005, ed. R. L. Gordon and Francisco Marco Simón (Leiden: Brill, 2010), 381–98; Daniel Ogden, “Binding Spells: Curse Tablets and Voodoo Dolls in the Greek and Roman Worlds,” in Witchcraft and Magic in Europe: Ancient Greece and Rome, ed. Bengt Ankarloo and Stuart Clark, Athlone History of Witchcraft and Magic in Europe 2 (London: Athlone, 1999), 3–90. ↵
- Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History, 183–93; Dan Levene, A Corpus of Magic Bowls: Incantation Texts in Jewish Aramaic from Late Antiquity (London: Kegan Paul, 2003). ↵
- This is a problematic term but remains the best way of referring to such objects in English. It is not meant to imply any association with contemporary religious practices found in Haiti, West Africa or elsewhere. See the remarks in Christopher A. Faraone, “Binding and Burying the Forces of Evil: The Defensive Use of ‘Voodoo Dolls’ in Ancient Greece,” Classical Antiquity 10.2 (1991): 65, n. 4, https://doi.org/10.2307/25010949. The term "poppet", whilst increasingly common, is inappropriate as it is a term of endearment in a number of dialects of British English. For examples of the use of such dolls see Horace, Satirae 1.8; Ovid, Heroides 6.83–94; Pseudo-Callisthenes, Historia Alexandri Magni 5; Theocritus, Idylls 2 (Pharmakon). ↵
- See, for example, Campbell Bonner, Studies in Magical Amulets: Chiefly Graeco-Egyptian (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1950); Roy Kotansky, Greek Magical Amulets: The Inscribed Gold, Silver, Copper, and Bronze Lamellae, Papyrologica Coloniensia 22.1 (Opladen: Westdeutscher, 1994). ↵
- Bonner, Studies in Magical Amulets: Chiefly Graeco-Egyptian; Simone Michel, Die magischen Gemmen: zu Bildern und Zauberformeln auf geschnittenen Steinen der Antike und Neuzeit (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2004); John G. Gager, ed., Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999); Kotansky, Greek Magical Amulets; Simone Michel, Peter Zazoff, and Hilde Zazoff, Die magischen Gemmen im Britischen Museum (London: British Museum Press, 2001); Daniel Ogden, ed., Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts in the Greek and Roman Worlds: A Sourcebook, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009); Hanna Philipp, Mira et magica : Gemmen im Ägyptischen Museum der Staatlichen Museen Preussischer Kulturbesitz, Berlin-Charlottenburg (Mainz am Rhein: von Zabern, 1986). ↵
- For studies of the use of objects in actual practice, see Magali Bailliot, Magie et sortilèges dans l’Antiquité romaine: Archéologie des rituels et des images (Paris: Editions Hermann, 2010); Andrew Wilburn, Materia Magica: The Archaeology of Magic in Roman Egypt, Cyprus, and Spain (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2012). ↵
- See, for example, the depiction of Circe and her wand found on a first-century CE pottery oil lamp from Pozzuoli, in the British Museum, in Donald M. Bailey, A Catalogue of the Lamps in the British Museum, 4 vols. (London: British Museum Publications, 1975), Q949. Such imagery was relatively common. Another example can be found in the Antikensammlungen, Munich. W. B. Stanford has argued that Circe's staff need not be interpreted as magical in the Odyssey. W. B. Stanford, “That Circe’s ῥάβδος (Od. 10, 238 Ff.) Was Not a Magic Wand,” Hermathena 66 (1945): 69–71. However, whilst this may be the case, subsequent receptions of the narrative were unanimous in understanding it in this way. For primary sources for Circe, see especially Homer, Od. 10.293, 388; Ovid, Metamorphoses 14.278, 413; Virgil, Aeneid 7.189–91. For the depictions of Medea in material culture, see Margot Schmidt, “Medea,” Lexicon Iconographicum Mythologiae Classicae, 1.386-398, 2.194-202. For Medea in primary sources see especially Apollonius Rhodius, Argonautica; Euripides, Medea; Hyginus, Fabulae 21–6; Ovid, Her. 12; Metam. 7.1–450; Pindar, Pythionikai 4; Seneca, Medea. See also the discussion of the Medea myth in James Joseph Clauss and Sarah Iles Johnston, eds., Medea: Essays on Medea in Myth, Literature, Philosophy and Art (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997); Emma Griffiths, Medea (London: Routledge, 2006). For the representation of witches in Roman art and literature more generally, see Luck, “Witches and Sorcerers in Classical Literature”; Pollard, “Witch-Crafting in Roman Literature and Art.” ↵
- For mosaics, J. R. C. Cousland, “The Much Suffering Eye in Antioch’s House of the Evil Eye: Is It Mithraic?,” Religious Studies and Theology 24.1 (2005): 61–74; Katherine M. D. Dunbabin, Mosaics of the Greek and Roman World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 312, 323–24. For amulets, Bonner, Studies in Magical Amulets: Chiefly Graeco-Egyptian, 97–100. For earrings, see, for example, the recent find of a Roman earring from Norwich featuring an evil eye being attacked and which probably had an apotropaic function (http://finds.org.uk/database/artefacts/record/id/490934 [Accessed 12 July 2023]). For useful discussions of the evil eye in the Roman empire, see Antón Alvar Nuño, “Ocular Pathologies and the Evil Eye in the Early Roman Principate,” Numen 59.4 (2012): 295–321, https://doi.org/10.1163/156852712X641769; Ari Z. Bryen and Andrzej Wypustek, “Gemellus’ Evil Eyes (P.Mich. VI 423–424),” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 49.4 (2010): 535–55; Matthew W. Dickie, “The Fathers of the Church and the Evil Eye,” in Byzantine Magic, ed. Henry Maguire (Washington, DC: Dumbarton Oaks, 1995), 9–34; John H. Elliott, “Social-Scientific Criticism: Perspective, Process and Payoff. Evil Eye Accusation at Galatia as Illustration of the Method,” HTS Teologiese Studies-Theological Studies 67.1 (2011), https://doi.org/10.4102/hts.v67i1.858; Elliott, “The Evil Eye and the Sermon on the Mount,” Biblical Interpretation: A Journal of Contemporary Approaches 2.1 (1994): 51–84, https://doi.org/10.1163/156851594X00042. For more general studies, see Frederick Thomas Elworthy, The Evil Eye: An Account of This Ancient and Widespread Superstition (London: J. Murray, 1895); Clarence Maloney, ed., The Evil Eye (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1976). See Catullus, 5, 7; Horace, Epist. 1.14.37–38; Pliny, Nat. 7.2.16–18, 28.7.39; Plutarch, Moralia 680c–683b; Strabo, Geographica 14.2.7, 654c; Virgil, Eclogae 3.103. ↵
- Corpus Inscriptionum Latinarum 6.19747; see Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 119. For a catalogue of inscriptions that make reference to, or might make reference to, untimely death as a result of witchcraft, see Fritz Graf, “Untimely Death, Witchcraft, and Divine Vengeance. A Reasoned Epigraphical Catalog,” Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 162 (2007): 139–50, https://doi.org/10.2307/20191339. ↵
- For socio-religious prohibitions against magic, see C. R. Phillips, “Nullum Crimen Sine Lege: Socioreligious Sanctions on Magic,” in Magika Hiera: Ancient Greek Magic and Religion, ed. Christopher A. Faraone and Dirk Obbink (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1991), 260–76. For legal prohibitions, see Derek Collins, Magic in the Ancient Greek World (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008), 132–65; Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 275–99; Clyde Pharr, “The Interdiction of Magic in Roman Law,” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 63 (1932): 269–95, https://doi.org/10.2307/283219; Ramsay MacMullen, Enemies of the Roman Order: Treason, Unrest and Alienation in the Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1966), 124–27; Rives, “Magic in Roman Law”; Rives, “Magic, Religion and Law: The Case of the Lex Cornelia de Sicariis et Veneficiis,” in Religion and Law in Classical and Christian Rome, ed. Clifford Ando and Jörg Rüpke (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 2006), 47–67. Magic, per se, was not a subject of legislation in Greek law, though actions that might be interpreted as magical could provoke a legal charge of ἀσέβεια (impiety). See Phillips, “Nullum Crimen Sine Lege: Socioreligious Sanctions on Magic,” 262. For an example of a legal accusation of magic during the Principate see P.Mich. VI.423 and 424 (Karanis, Roman Egypt, 197 CE); discussed in Bryen and Wypustek, “Gemellus’ Evil Eyes (P.Mich. VI 423–424)”; David Frankfurter, “Fetus Magic and Sorcery Fears in Roman Egypt,” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 46.1 (2006): 37–62. ↵
- Notably Sulla's Lex Cornelia de sicariis et veneficiis (81 BCE). See Paulus, Sententiae 5.23.15–18. ↵
- Stratton, Naming the Witch: Magic, Ideology, and Stereotype in the Ancient World, 107. See, for example, Irenaeus, Adversus haereses 1.4.7, 1.13.1–6, 2.31.2–3, 2.32. See also Todd Breyfogle, “Magic, Women, and Heresy in the Late Empire: The Case of the Priscillianists,” in Ancient Magic and Ritual Power, ed. Marvin W. Meyer and Paul A. Mirecki (Leiden: Brill, 1995), 435–54. Interestingly this was not the case in Second Temple Judaism. See Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History, 76. ↵
- See, for example, Bonner, Studies in Magical Amulets: Chiefly Graeco-Egyptian, 123–39. See plates viii and ix. Such gems are often associated with the second-century Christian gnostic Basilides or gnosticism more generally, but it is unwise to assume an exclusive or even primary identification of Abraxas/Abrasax and gnostic thought and practice; the deity appears to have had much wider appeal and non-gnostic origins. See L. Janssens, “L’apport de Perse aux études néroniennes. Abrasax, le dieu de Néron,” in Neronia 1977: actes du 2e Colloque de la Société internationale d’études néroniennes, Clermont-Ferrand, 27-28 mai 1977, ed. Jean-Michel Croisille and P.-M. Fauchère (Clermont-Ferrand: ADOSA, 1982), 191–222. See also A. A. Barb, “Abrasax-Studien,” Latomus 28 (1957): 67–86; A. A. Barb, “Gnostische, Gemme,” Enciclopedia dell’ Arte Antica, Classica e Orientale 3:971–74; J. R. Harrison, “Overcoming the ‘Strong Man,’” in New Documents Illustrating Early Christianity: Volume 10, ed. S. R. Llewelyn and J. R. Harrison (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2012), 11; Martin Persson Nilsson, “The Anguipede of the Magical Amulets,” Harvard Theological Review 44.1 (1951): 61–64. ↵
- For such amulets see, for example, Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History, 213. Solomon's power over demons is found in a number of textual traditions. See, for example, Josephus, Antiquitates judaicae 8.42–45; Testament of Solomon. See also Mary Margaret Fulghum, “Coins Used as Amulets in Late Antiquity,” in Between Magic and Religion: Interdisciplinary Studies in Ancient Mediterranean Religion and Society, ed. Sulochana Ruth Asirvatham and John Watrous (Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 142–43; Klutz, Rewriting the Testament of Solomon. ↵
- This is, perhaps, particularly true for scholars of early Christianity, for whom material culture directly relevant to their field is thin on the ground before the conversion of Constantine. For useful analyses of the scant data relating to the ante pacem church, see Ramsay MacMullen, The Second Church: Popular Christianity A.D. 200-400 (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2009); Graydon F. Snyder, Ante Pacem: Archaeological Evidence of Church Life before Constantine, 2nd ed. (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1985). ↵
- Betz, The Greek Magical Papyri, xli. ↵
- Scott B. Noegel, Joel T. Walker, and Brannon M. Wheeler, “Introduction,” in Prayer, Magic, and the Stars in the Ancient and Late Antique World, ed. Scott B. Noegel, Joel Thomas Walker, and Brannon M. Wheeler (University Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 2003), 12. ↵
- Indeed, some have suggested that "magic" should cease to be used as an analytical category on these grounds. David Pocock, for example, has argued that "if categorical distinctions of the Western mind are found upon examination to impose distinctions upon (and so falsify) the intellectual universes of other cultures then they must be discarded or, as I have put it, dissolved. I believe 'magic' to be one such category." David F. Pocock, “Foreword,” in A General Theory of Magic, by Marcel Mauss, trans. Robert Brain, 2nd ed. (London: Routledge, 1972), 2. Most in the field reject the notion that "magic" is a universally applicable category. See, for example, Alan F. Segal, “Hellenistic Magic: Some Questions of Definition,” in Studies in Gnosticism and Hellenistic Religions Presented to Gilles Quispel on the Occasion of His 65th Birthday, ed. R. van der Broek and M. J. Vermaseren (Leiden: Brill, 1981), 50–51; Jonathan Z. Smith, “Trading Places,” in Ancient Magic and Ritual Power, ed. Marvin Meyer and Paul Mirecki (Leiden: Brill, 1995), 16. For studies of the discursive contexts within which "magic" emerged as a discrete analytical category, see Randall Styers, Making Magic: Religion, Magic, and Science in the Modern World, Reflection and Theory in the Study of Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004); Stanley J. Tambiah, Magic, Science and Religion and the Scope of Rationality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). ↵
- For example, Betz declares, "a definition of the notion of magic cannot be attempted here". Betz, The Greek Magical Papyri, xlix, n. 6. Whilst Betz does refer the reader to some literature on the subject, it is a little surprising that in a book concerned with magic, of over three hundred and fifty pages in length, he does not attempt such a thing. This does result in some confusion. For example, at the outset of his work, Betz equates the burning of magical books in Acts 19.19 with the burning of books of prophecy, including forged Sibylline oracles, by Augustus in 13 BCE (Suetonius, Divus Augustus 31.1). The two are not obviously comparable. The latter may have been regarded as threatening and seditious, but it is not evident that such books would have been considered magical — after all the authentic Sibylline oracles (some of which were saved from the conflagration) were a central and revered aspect of Roman religion. See H. W. Parke, Sibyls and Sibylline Prophecy in Classical Antiquity. (London: Routledge, 1988). A better parallel is found in Paulus, Sent. 5.23.18. ↵
- Ogden refuses to provide a definition of magic for his important sourcebook on the subject. The contents of his work are determined by "the subject matter of recent scholarly books on antiquity with such words as 'magic' in their titles". Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 5. ↵
- As Cicero notes, "I know of no people, whether they be learned and refined or barbaric and ignorant, that does not consider that future things are indicated by signs, and that it is possible for certain people to recognise those signs and predict what will happen." (De divinatione 1.2). See, for example, Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Antiquitates Romanae 4.62; Livy 1.18.6–10; Lucan, Pharsalia 1.605–38; Plutarch, Numa 7. ↵
- See, for example, Sarah Iles Johnston, Ancient Greek Divination (Oxford: Wiley Blackwell, 2008); Sarah Iles Johnston and Peter T. Struck, eds., Mantikê: Studies in Ancient Divination, Religions in the Graeco-Roman World 155 (Leiden: Brill, 2005). ↵
- For the centrality of divination in Roman religion, see the remarks of Cotta in Cicero, De natura deorum 3.2. See also Livy 6.41. ↵
- F. Gerald Downing, “Magic and Scepticism in and around the First Christian Century,” in Making Sense in (and of) the First Christian Century, JSNTSup 197 (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 2000), 208–22. Downing includes in his discussion of "oracular magic" the criticism of haruspices found in Cicero's De divinatione, which included Cato's famous quip that he was surprised a haruspex did not burst out laughing when he saw another one (Div. 2.24.52). Cicero's own position on the matter is rather more equivocal than is often assumed. It seems most likely that he was opposed to private divination (as were others, see Suetonius, Tiberius 63.1) and believed it was an example of superstitio, but approved of the official, public interpretation of portents as an acceptable element of religio (appropriate honouring of the gods). See, for example, Div. 2.72.148 and the discussion in Susanne William Rasmussen, Public Portents in Republican Rome, Analecta Romana Instituti Danici. Supplementum 34 (Rome: L’Erma di Bretschneider, 2003), 215. Even when the haruspices are criticised in De Divinatione they are not criticised for practising magic. Downing's interpretation has more in common with that of the fourth-century Christian emperor Constantius II who did not distinguish between traditional haruspices, astrologers, dream interpreters and magicians when outlawing pagan divinatory practices. See Marie Theres Fögen, “Balsamon on Magic: From Roman Secular Law to Byzantine Canon Law,” in Byzantine Magic, ed. Henry Maguire (Washington, DC: Dumbarton Oaks, 1995), 103. See also Codex justinianus 9.18.3 (Constantine, 319 CE), 5 (Constantius II, 357 CE), 7 (Constantius II, 358 CE). Note Lucan's clear distinction between such practices that whilst arcane, were lawful, and "the mysteries of cruel witchcraft, which the gods abhor" (Lucan, Phars. 6.431). A similar distinction is also made in Dio Cassius 52.36.1–2. ↵
- As Rives rightly notes,
Since divination has been rigorously excluded from the dominant religious traditions of Europe and the Middle East ever since the conversion of Constantine, many people are now apt to think of it as mere fortune-telling, a way of looking in to the future. This was of course important, but there was generally more to it than that. […] Divination was … an essential complement to prayer and sacrifice, completing the circle of communication between gods and mortals. (James B. Rives, Religion in the Roman Empire [Oxford: Blackwell, 2007], 27)
↵ - See, for example, Marie-Laurence Haack, Les haruspices dans le monde romain, vol. 6 of Scripta Antiqua (Pessac: Ausonius, 2003); Bruce MacBain, Prodigy and Expiation: A Study in Religion and Politics in Republican Rome, Collection Latomus 177 (Bruxelles: Latomus, 1982); John A. North, “Diviners and Divination at Rome,” in Pagan Priests: Religion and Power in the Ancient World, ed. Mary Beard and John A. North (London: Duckworth, 1990), 51–71; John Scheid, An Introduction to Roman Religion, trans. Janet Lloyd (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2003), 111–26. ↵
- See, for example, Robert E. A. Palmer, “Bullae Insignia Ingenuitatis,” American Journal of Ancient History 14.1 (1998): 1–69. See Macrobius, Saturnalia 1.6.7–13; Pliny, Nat. 33.4.10; Plutarch, Romulus 20.3, 25.5. Amulets were not understood en masse as "magical" in the early Roman empire, although some were, by virtue of their specific form and the use to which they were put. The blanket designation of them as such by some is unhelpful. See, for example, Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 261; Roy Kotansky, “Incantations and Prayers on Inscribed Greek Amulets,” in Magika Hiera: Ancient Greek Magic and Religion, ed. Christopher A. Faraone and Dirk Obbink (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 113–14. Pliny the Elder, for instance, clearly distinguished between magic, the "most fraudulent of arts" (Nat. 30.1.1; cf. 28.12.48), to which he was strongly opposed, and the production and use of numerous amulets that he described, without criticism, in his Naturalis historia. Indeed, he singled some out as efficacious, and particularly helpful when employed where conventional medicine was unlikely to succeed. See for example, Nat. 30.30. See also Maria Cristina Martini, Piante medicamentose e rituali magico-religiosi in Plinio (Rome: Bulzoni, 1977). Likewise, Trajan could endorse a medical text for his legions that recommended the use of amulets, evidently perceiving such things to be clearly distinguishable from magic. Vivian Nutton, Ancient Medicine (London: Routledge, 2004), 269. Ammianus Marcellinus' shock at the outlawing, in the late fourth century, of traditional, doctor-approved charms, is indicative of how such things were not considered magical in the earlier period (see Ammianus Marcellinus 16.8.1, 19.12.14). Even those medical writers who rejected the reasoning that lay behind amulets, such as the often rather arcane notions of sympathy and antipathy which most employed, could still view them as potentially beneficial to a patient's sense of well-being (see Soranus, Gynaeceia 3.42). Amulets were ubiquitous and their use was largely uncontroversial. Indeed, those who rejected the use of amulets to protect themselves from disease were sufficiently eccentric as to be considered mad (Scriptores Historiae Augustae, Caracalla 5, 7). To judge from the archaeological record, almost everyone carried an amulet to aid digestion and ward off such things as fever. See Bonner, Studies in Magical Amulets: Chiefly Graeco-Egyptian, 51–66. ↵
- See Cato, De agricultura 160. Also referred to in Pliny, Nat. 17.47.267. See Eric Laughton, “Cato’s Charm for Dislocations,” The Classical Review 52.2 (1938): 52–54, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009840X00073066; W B McDaniel, “A Sempiternal Superstition. For a Dislocated Joint, a Split Green Reed, and a Latin Charm,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 15.2 (1972): 295–306; H. S. Versnel, “The Poetics of the Magical Charm. An Essay on the Power of Words,” in Magic and Ritual in the Ancient World, ed. Paul Allan Mirecki and Marvin W. Meyer (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 105–58. ↵
- Our earliest source for Roman law, the Lex Duodecim Tabularum from the fifth century BCE outlawed specific practices — harmful incantations and the enchanting of crops — rather than magic per se (XII Tab. 8). See Cicero, Orationes philippicae 1.44; R. Westbrook, “The Nature and Origins of the Twelve Tables,” Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte, Romanistische Abteilung 105 (1988): 74–121. However, such practices "were later reconceptualized as instances of magic". Rives, Religion in the Roman Empire, 317. By about the first century BCE magic itself was believed by the Romans to have always been outlawed. See also Matthew W. Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World (London: Routledge, 2002), 124–41; Richard Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” in Witchcraft and Magic in Europe: Ancient Greece and Rome, ed. Bengt Ankarloo and Stuart Clark, Athlone History of Witchcraft and Magic in Europe 2 (London: Athlone, 1999), 164–65, 207, and 229–31. ↵
- Attilio Mastrocinque, Kronos, Shiva, and Asklepios: Studies in Magical Gems and Religions of the Roman Empire (Philadelphia, PA: American Philosophical Society, 2011), 4. ↵
- Mastrocinque, Kronos, Shiva, and Asklepios, 5. For Asklepios, see Emma J. Edelstein and Ludwig Edelstein, eds., Asclepius: Collection and Interpretation of the Testimonies (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998); Alexia Petsalis-Diomidis, Truly beyond Wonders: Aelius Aristides and the Cult of Asklepios (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010). Studies of the imperial cult are legion. Notable contributions include: Jeffrey Brodd and Jonathan L. Reed, eds., Rome and Religion: A Cross-Disciplinary Dialogue on the Imperial Cult (Atlanta, GA: Society of Biblical Literature, 2011); Ittai Gradel, Emperor Worship and Roman Religion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002); S. R. F. Price, Rituals and Power : The Roman Imperial Cult in Asia Minor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). ↵
- Sarah Iles Johnston, “Review Article: Describing the Undefinable: New Books on Magic and Old Problems of Definition,” History of Religions 43.1 (2003): 50. It should be noted that Johnston herself makes a convincing plea for the need to attempt a definition of magic. For a valuable critique of analogous debates about "religion" and the danger of exaggerating the importance of definitional issues, see Steve Bruce, “Defining Religion: A Practical Response,” International Review of Sociology: Revue Internationale de Sociologie 21.1 (2011): 107–20, https://doi.org/10.1080/03906701.2011.544190. ↵
- Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 18. ↵
- Bruce Kapferer, “Introduction: Outside All Reason — Magic, Sorcery and Epistemology in Anthropology,” in Beyond Rationalism: Rethinking Magic, Witchcraft, and Sorcery, ed. Bruce Kapferer (New York, NY: Berghahn Books, 2003), 1. ↵
- For helpful surveys of the contours of the debate, see Graham Cunningham, Religion and Magic: Approaches and Theories (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999); Bernd-Christian Otto and Michael Stausberg, eds., “Defining Magic: A Reader” (Sheffield: Equinox, 2012); Rebecca Stein and Philip L. Stein, The Anthropology of Religion, Magic, and Witchcraft, 3rd ed. (Harlow: Pearson, 2011); Murray Wax and Rosalie Wax, “The Notion of Magic,” Current Anthropology 4.5 (1963): 495–518. It would be invidious to single out any particular contributions, but the recent reflexive turn has revitalised the definitional debate considerably. See, for example, Susan Greenwood, The Anthropology of Magic (New York, NY: Berg, 2009); Galina Lindquist, Conjuring Hope: Healing and Magic in Contemporary Russia (New York, NY: Berghahn Books, 2006); Harry G. West, Ethnographic Sorcery (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2007). ↵
- For critical surveys of theories of magic, see Cunningham, Religion and Magic: Approaches and Theories; Ariel Glucklich, The End of Magic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 3–81; Malcolm B. Hamilton, The Sociology of Religion: Theoretical and Comparative Perspectives, 2nd ed. (London: Routledge, 2001), 39–54; Daniel Lawrence O’Keefe, Stolen Lightning: The Social Theory of Magic (New York, NY: Random House, 1983); Tambiah, Magic, Science and Religion and the Scope of Rationality; Wax and Wax, “The Notion of Magic.” ↵
- Essentialist or substantive definitions of magic assume that there is something distinctive about magic, in particular characteristics that distinguish it from religion or science. Such definitions have been put forward, albeit in very different ways, by, for example, E. E. Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1937); James George Frazer, The Golden Bough: A Study in Comparative Religion., 2 vols. (London: Macmillan, 1890); Mischa Titiev, “A Fresh Approach to the Problem of Magic and Religion,” Southwestern Journal of Anthropology 16.3 (1960): 292–98, https://doi.org/10.2307/3629032; Edward B. Tylor, Primitive Culture: Researches into the Development of Mythology, Philosophy, Religion, Art, and Custom, 2 vols. (London: J. Murray, 1871). See also more recent studies, such as Greenwood, The Anthropology of Magic. ↵
- Functionalist definitions emphasise the social or psychological functions of magic, such as that found in Bronislaw Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion, and Other Essays (Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1948). Frustratingly Durkheim, the leading functionalist, did not provide a definition of magic although he wrote much about it. For him, magic was essentially the opposite of religion. For example, for Durkheim religions create social life and form moral communities but magic is antithetical to such social and moral life. See Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life: A Study in Religious Sociology, trans. Joseph Ward Swain (London: Allen & Unwin, 1915), 42–49. ↵
- Locative-relational definitions of magic define magic relative to something else, and its concomitant location. Mauss provides a good example of such a definition:
A magical rite is any rite which does not play a part in organised cult […] We do not define magic in terms of the structure of its rites, but by the circumstances in which these rites occur, which in turn determine the place they occupy in the totality of social customs. (Marcel Mauss, Esquisse d’une théorie générale de la magie [Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1902], 24)
↵ - The notion that magic is a stage in human development is found in Frazer, The Golden Bough: A Study in Comparative Religion.; Tylor, Primitive Culture; Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, ed. G. Roth and C. Wittich, trans. E. Fischoff (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1978). For a survey of such evolutionary approaches, see Styers, Making Magic. ↵
- Developmental interpretations of magic can take a number of forms. For example, it is often argued that "magical thinking" — the conviction that a person's thoughts directly affect the world — is particularly associated with bereavement and childhood. See, for example, Joan Didion, The Year of Magical Thinking (New York, NY: Knopf, 2006); Jean Piaget, The Child’s Conception of the World, trans. Joan Tomlinson and Andrew Tomlinson (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1929). Lewis has also suggested that conceptualisations of magic may alter over the general course of a person's life, as a result of both individual experience and the effect of the different roles that accompany various phases of adulthood. To put it succinctly, we need to understand magic in a way that accounts for the fact that "people change their opinions as they grow older". Gilbert Lewis, “The Look of Magic,” Man 21.3 (1986): 414, https://doi.org/10.2307/2803094. ↵
- The term "intellectualist" is one particularly used of James Frazer and Edward Tylor. See Frazer, The Golden Bough: A Study in Comparative Religion.; Tylor, Primitive Culture. However, it is also employed for more recent scholars, such as Robin Horton. See Robin Horton, Patterns of Thought in Africa and the West: Essays on Magic, Religion and Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). "Intellectualist" refers to those scholars who view magic (and religion) as something employed by people to explain puzzling aspects of the world about them; something that is "essentially rational" even though it provides explanations that are "crude and fallacious". A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive Society: Essays and Addresses (London: Cohen & West, 1961), 20. See Cunningham, Religion and Magic: Approaches and Theories, 15. ↵
- Although one of the founding figures in functionalism, Malinowski's understanding of magic can also be termed instrumentalist. For him, magic was "a practical art consisting of acts which are only means to a definite end expected to follow later on". Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion, 68. ↵
- This is the label given by Ogden to conceptualisations of magic that are derived from the use of one or more magical terms within a chosen society. See Daniel Ogden, Greek and Roman Necromancy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004), xviii–xix. ↵
- Tambiah, for example, argues, using the work of Austin, that magic is a kind of "performative utterance", that is an illocutionary act which itself changes reality. See John Langshaw Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Tambiah, Magic, Science and Religion and the Scope of Rationality; Tambiah, “The Magical Power of Words,” Man 3.2 (1968): 175–208, https://doi.org/10.2307/2798500. ↵
- For example, Marrett understood magic to arise "from the emotion of tension and is cathartic or stimulating, providing relief or encouragement when technical methods are inadequate". Cunningham, Religion and Magic: Approaches and Theories, 24. See R. R. Marett, The Threshold of Religion, 2nd ed. (London: Methuen, 1914). For a contemporary example of such an approach, see Lindquist, Conjuring Hope. ↵
- For example, Kapferer, “Introduction: Outside All Reason — Magic, Sorcery and Epistemology in Anthropology.” ↵
- For example, Gerardus van der Leeuw, Religion in Essence and Manifestation, trans. J. E. Turner (London: Allen & Unwin, 1938); Paul Stoller, Fusion of the Worlds: An Ethnography of Possession among the Songhay of Niger (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1989); West, Ethnographic Sorcery. ↵
- For example, Greenwood, The Anthropology of Magic. ↵
- For example, Glucklich, The End of Magic. ↵
- The classic summary of this position can be found in William J. Goode, “Magic and Religion: A Continuum,” Ethnos 14.2 (1949): 172–82, https://doi.org/10.1080/00141844.1949.9980699. Although very critical of the motivations that lay behind those who insisted, for ideological reasons, on a distinction between "magic" and "religion", he still found that such a distinction had analytical utility. Aune's influential study of magic in antiquity assumes a traditional, essentialist, dichotomy between magic and religion, despite claims to the contrary in his text. David E. Aune, “Magic in Early Christianity,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. II.23.2, ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1980), 1507–57. This is something that Hutton has rightly noted. See Ronald Hutton, Witches, Druids and King Arthur (London: Bloomsbury, 2006), 103. For a significant critique of attempts to distinguish "magic" and "religion", see Dorothy Hammond, “Magic: A Problem in Semantics,” American Anthropologist 72.6 (1970): 1349–56, https://doi.org/10.1525/aa.1970.72.6.02a00080. For criticisms of essentialist and substantive interpretations see, for example, H. S. Versnel, “Some Reflections on the Relationship Magic-Religion,” Numen 38.2 (1991): 177–97, https://doi.org/10.1163/156852791X00114; Smith, “Trading Places.” ↵
- Smith, “Trading Places,” 227. To be fair to Smith, his remarks relate specifically to the Papyri Graecae Magicae (ibid. 222) and he is not explicitly claiming that his observations have any saliency beyond the analysis of that corpus of texts (however, as with much of what Smith has to say, they have been understood to have more wide-ranging implications). The "miniaturisation" of ritual could be said to be a characteristic of everyday private and domestic devotion in antiquity and not something that should be seen as an unusual or distinguishing feature of the Papyri Graecae Magicae. For Roman domestic religion, see J. R. Clarke, The Houses of Roman Italy, 100 B.C.– A.D. 250: Ritual, Space, and Decoration (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1991); Annemarie Kaufmann-Heinimann, “Religion in the House,” in A Companion to Roman Religion, ed. Jörg Rüpke (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2007), 188–201; David Gerald Orr, “Roman Domestic Religion: A Study of the Roman Household Deities and Their Shrines at Pompeii and Herculaneum” (PhD thesis, University of Maryland, 1972); Orr, “Roman Domestic Religion: The Archaeology of Roman Popular Art,” in Rituals and Ceremonies in Popular Culture, ed. Ray B. Browne (Bowling Green, OH: Popular Press, 1980), 88–104; Orr, “Roman Domestic Religion: The Evidence of the Household Shrines,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt, II.16.2, ed. Wolfgang Haase and Hildegard Temporini (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1978), 1557–91. For the use of statuettes in private and domestic devotion, see Plutarch, Sulla 29.6; Ammianus Marcellinus 22.13.3; Apuleius, Apol. 63.2. ↵
- As, for example, Morton Smith rightly observes:
Private dealings with supernatural beings make up most of what we call "magic" as well as what we call "private religion". There is no clear line between the two. When we compare avowedly religious texts and reports of religious practices with the texts of the magical papyri and the practices they prescribe, we find the same goals stated and the same means used. For instance, spells for destruction of an enemy are commonly supposed to be magical, but there are many in the Psalms. The cliché, that the religious man petitions the gods while the magician tries to compel them, is simply false. (Morton Smith, Jesus the Magician [San Francisco, CA: Harper & Row, 1978], 69)
↵ - The trenchant criticisms of functionalist definitions of religion made by Bruce are applicable to functionalist definitions of magic. See Bruce, “Defining Religion,” 111–12. ↵
- James A. Francis, Subversive Virtue: Asceticism and Authority in the Second-Century Pagan World (University Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 2008), 90. ↵
- See Bronislaw Malinowski, “Culture,” Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences IV:638. ↵
- See S. F. Nadel, “Malinowski on Magic and Religion,” in Man and Culture: An Evaluation of the Work of Bronislaw Malinowski, ed. Raymond Firth (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1957), 189–208. ↵
- For example, Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 24–25; Marcel Mauss, A General Theory of Magic, trans. Robert Brain (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972), 24. Such a perspective is succinctly described by Crossan: "Religion is official and approved magic; magic is unofficial and unapproved religion. More simply: 'we' practice religion, 'they' practice magic." John Dominic Crossan, The Historical Jesus: The Life of a Mediterranean Jewish Peasant (San Francisco, CA: HarperSanFrancisco, 1991), 304. ↵
- Whether that be religious or secular and scientific. See Olof Pettersson, “Magic — Religion: Some Marginal Notes to an Old Problem,” Ethnos 22.3 (1957): 109–19; Tambiah, Magic, Science and Religion and the Scope of Rationality; Styers, Making Magic. ↵
- A point made by Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History, 62. ↵
- A similar point is made in Smith, “Trading Places.” ↵
- Evans-Pritchard's study of the Azande provides a famous example of this. According to his account, the Azande possess no substantive religious beliefs, rituals or institutions, relative to which their magic can be defined. See Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande. ↵
- Hutton, Witches, Druids and King Arthur, 312. ↵
- A point made by O’Keefe, Stolen Lightning: The Social Theory of Magic, 10. For analysis of Weber's understanding of magic, see Stefan Breuer, “Magie, Zauber, Entzauberung,” in Max Webers >>Religionssystematik<<, ed. Hans G. Kippenberg and Martin Riesebrodt (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2001), 119–30. The same, as we have already noted, could also be said of Durkheim. ↵
- Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive Society, 138. He suggested the same for the term "religion". ↵
- See, for example, Marvin W. Meyer and Richard Smith, eds., “Ancient Christian Magic: Coptic Texts of Ritual Power” (San Francisco, CA: Harper Collins, 1999), 1–6; Smith, “Trading Places.” For a criticism of this practice see Bohak, Ancient Jewish Magic: A History, 61; C. A. Hoffman, “Fiat Magia,” in Magic and Ritual in the Ancient World, ed. Paul Allan Mirecki and Marvin W. Meyer, Religions in the Graeco-Roman World 141 (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 179–94. ↵
- Alan Dundes, “Wet and Dry, the Evil Eye: An Essay in Indo-European and Semitic Worldview,” in The Evil Eye: A Casebook, ed. Alan Dundes (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981), 258. ↵
- Rodney Stark, “Reconceptualizing Religion, Magic, and Science,” Review of Religious Research 43.2 (2001): 102, https://doi.org/10.2307/3512057. ↵
- Versnel, “Some Reflections on the Relationship Magic-Religion,” 181. Although Versnel's words were published over thirty years ago, they accurately describe the current state of scholarship in the field. ↵
- Hutton, Witches, Druids and King Arthur, 106. Although, as Hutton has noted, in his useful survey of the classical scholarship on the subject, a form of the traditional, essentialist, dichotomy between magic and religion, in which the former is seen as manipulative and coercive and the latter supplicatory, has persisted, even in works by authors who have explicitly rejected it. See Hutton, Witches, Druids and King Arthur, 98–103. See also Versnel, “Some Reflections on the Relationship Magic-Religion.” ↵
- See Herbert Blumer, Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Method. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1969), 148. ↵
- See, for example, Paulus, Sent. 5.23.14–19. ↵
- Attilio Mastrocinque, “Creating One’s Own Religion: Intellectual Choices,” in A Companion to Roman Religion, ed. Jörg Rüpke (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2007), 387. Although this does not mean that there were not a number of theories of magic in antiquity, as Graf has demonstrated in Fritz Graf, “Theories of Magic in Antiquity,” in Magic and Ritual in the Ancient World, ed. Paul Allan Mirecki and Marvin W. Meyer (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 93–104. ↵
- Apuleius, Apol. 25. Indeed, as Rives has persuasively argued, it was precisely through such trials as that of Apuleius that definitions of magic were thrashed out and developed over time. See Rives, “Magic, Religion and Law,” 65. See also Rives, “Magic in Roman Law.” ↵
- For the Latin terminology associated with magic, see Eli Edward Burriss, “The Terminology of Witchcraft,” Classical Philology 31.2 (1936): 137–45, https://doi.org/10.2307/264710. See also Jan N. Bremmer, “The Birth of the Term ‘Magic,’” in The Metamorphosis of Magic from Late Antiquity to the Early Modern Period, ed. Jan N. Bremmer and Jan R. Veenstra (Leuven: Peeters, 2002), 1–11. ↵
- See Ogden, Greek and Roman Necromancy, xviii–xix. ↵
- For polythetic definitions see Rodney Needham, “Polythetic Classification: Convergence and Consequences,” Man 10.3 (1975): 349–69, https://doi.org/10.2307/2799807. For the use of polythetic definitions in the study of religion see especially Jonathan Z. Smith, “Fences and Neighbors: Some Contours of Early Judaism,” in Imagining Religion: From Babylon to Jonestown, 2nd ed. (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 1–18; Brian C. Wilson, “From the Lexical to the Polythetic: A Brief History of the Definition of Religion,” in What Is Religion?: Origins, Definitions, and Explanations, ed. Thomas A. Idinopoulos and Brian C. Wilson (Leiden: Brill, 1998), 141–62. For the use of polythetic definitions of magic in antiquity, see Rives, “Magic in Roman Law,” 317; Versnel, “Some Reflections on the Relationship Magic-Religion,” 182–87. ↵
- See, for example, Morton Beckner, The Biological Way of Thought. (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1959), 22. Whilst monothetic definitions identify one or more distinguishing feature as necessary for classification, polythetic definitions include a number of features which, by themselves, are neither necessary or sufficient but are commonly occurring amongst a classification. Smith is wrong to maintain that polythetic definitions retain "the notion of necessary but abandoned the notion of sufficient criteria for admission to a class". Smith, “Fences and Neighbors,” 4. In polythetic definitions there are no characteristics which need to be found in every member of a class. It should also be noted that polythetic definitions have come in for significant criticism in the biological sciences. See, for example, J. P. Sutcliffe, “On the Logical Necessity and Priority of a Monothetic Conception of Class, and on the Consequent Inadequacy of Polythetic Accounts of Category and Categorization,” in New Approaches in Classification and Data Analysis, ed. Edwin Diday et al. (Berlin: Springer, 1994), 55–63. ↵
- Wilson, “From the Lexical to the Polythetic: A Brief History of the Definition of Religion,” 158. ↵
- That is, "the insider's or native's perspective of reality". David M. Fetterman, Ethnography: Step-by-Step, 3rd ed. (Los Angeles, CA: Sage, 2010), 20. ↵
- Though any claim to provide an emic account, even of the most rudimentary kind, is obviously not without its problems. See Thomas N. Headland, Kenneth Pike, and Marvin Harris, eds., Emics and Etics: The Insider/Outsider Debate (London: Sage, 1991). ↵
- Apollonius Rhodius, Argonautica 3.1026; Apuleius, Metam. 3.20, Apol. 42; Cicero, Pro Cluentio 194; Diodorus Siculus 4.52; Horace, Epodi 5; Hippocrates, De morbo sacro 1.38; Ovid, Metam. 7.179, Amores 1.8.1–20. See H. G. Kippenberg, “Magic in Roman Civil Discourse: Why Rituals Could Be Illegal,” in Envisioning Magic: A Princeton Seminar and Symposium, ed. Peter Schäfer and H. G. Kippenberg, Studies in the History of Religions 75 (Leiden: Brill, 1997), 137–64. ↵
- Apuleius, Apol. 26, 38; Eusebius, Contra Hieroclem 2.27; Lucian, Philopseudes 12, 35, Dialogi meretricii 288–89; Menippus 9; Virgil, Ecl. 8.64–109. ↵
- For human sacrifice see Cicero, In Vatinium 14; Horace, Epod. 5; CIL VI.19747; Paulus, Sent. 5.23.14–19; Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.11; cf. also Livy 25.1. Human sacrifice had been an element of the public cult of Rome, although this had ceased by the second century BCE. See Zsuzsanna Várhelyi, “The Specters of Roman Imperialism: The Live Burials of Gauls and Greeks at Rome,” Classical Antiquity 26.2 (2007): 277–304, https://doi.org/10.1525/ca.2007.26.2.277. ↵
- As, for example, Libo Drusus and Claudia Pulchra were accused of so doing (Tacitus, Ann. 2.27–32, 4.52). ↵
- For example, Apuleius, Apol. 26; Metam. 1.8, 2.21; Pseudo-Callisthenes, Alex. 3–4; Lucian, Men. 6; Maximus Tyrius, Dissertationes 8.2; Dio Cassius 56.23; Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 4.25. For a comprehensive treatment of different magical specialists in the Graeco-Roman world, see Daniel Ogden, Night’s Black Agents: Witches Wizards and the Dead in the Ancient World (London: Hambledon Continuum, 2008); Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 9–145. ↵
- For example, Lucan, Phars. 6.413–507; Ovid, Her. 6.83–94. ↵
- For example, Calypso in Homer, Od. 1.11–19, 5.151–58. See also Lucan, Phars. 6.624–830; Lucian, Philops. 17, 22–24; Ovid, Metam. 7.159–321; Pseudo-Quintilian, Declamationes maiores 10.19; Supplementum epigraphicum Graecum IX.72.110–21. ↵
- See, for example, Apuleius, Metam. 3.16–17; Cicero, Clu. 194; Clement of Alexandria, Protrepticus 2.22; Lucan, Phars. 6.570; Ovid, Am. 1.8.13; Metam. 7.193; Tibullus, Elegiae 1.2.42–66. ↵
- Ovid, Metam. 7.179; Petronius, Sat. 61–62. The period around a full moon could also be significant. See Heliodorus, Aethiopica 6.14; Lucian, Philops. 14. ↵
- For lunar eclipses, associated with the magical practice of "drawing down the moon"; see Plutarch, Mor. 145cd; Zenobius, Epitome proverbiorum Tarrhaei et Didymi 404. See Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 236–37. ↵
- Pliny, Nat. 28.27.92–106; Ovid, Metam. 7.238–93; Horace, Epod. 5; Apuleius, Metam. 2.21–30, 3.17; Apol. 30; Lucan, Phars. 6.507–830. See also Cyranides. ↵
- See Apuleius, Metam. 3.17; Ovid, Fasti 2.533–638; Petronius, Sat. 131; Theocritus, Id. 2. ↵
- See, for example, Apuleius, Metam. 3.15–25; Horace, Epod. 17; Lucan, Phars. 6.413–587; Lucian, Philops. 33–36. ↵
- For example, Apollonius Rhodius, Argonautica 3.1026–1062, 1191–1224; Hippocrates, Morb. Sacr. 4.32; Horace, Sat. 1.8; Lucian, Men. 9, Philops. 22–24; Ovid, Metam. 7.174, 194; Theocritus, Id. 2; Tibullus, Eleg. 1.2.42–66. For defixiones invoking Hecate that date from the early Roman empire, see Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 180–84. ↵
- Apuleius, Metam. 3.17, Apol. 63; Horace, Epod. 5; Sat. 1.8; Lucan, Phars. 6.624–830; Tertullian, De anima 56–57. Magic was not necessarily associated with demons in the early Roman empire. The relationship between daimones and humans in the classical world was an ambivalent one. For a survey, see Valerie Flint, “The Demonisation of Magic and Sorcery in Late Antiquity: Christian Redefinitions of Pagan Religions,” in Witchcraft and Magic in Europe: Ancient Greece and Rome, ed. Bengt Ankarloo and Stuart Clark, Athlone History of Witchcraft and Magic in Europe 2 (London: Athlone, 1999), 281–92. Although demons could be associated with magic (for example, Apuleius, Apol. 43), and equated with the spirits of the dead (for example, Apuleius, De deo Socratico 15), they only became prominent in the broader culture of the empire, and understood as consistently malign, as a result of the influence of Judaism and emergent Christianity, traditions that also helped to introduce angels into the eclectic repertoire of supernatural powers employed by magicians, something evident from the Papyri Graecae Magicae. For demonology in the early Roman Empire, see Frederick E. Brenk, “In the Light of the Moon : Demonology in the Early Imperial Period,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. II.16.3, ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1986), 2068–2145. For early Christianity, see Samuel Eitrem, Some Notes on the Demonology in the New Testament, 2nd ed., Symbolae Osloenses Fasciculi Suppletorii 20 (Oslo: Almqvist & Wiksells, 1966). ↵
- For the common picture that magic was harmful see, for example, Apuleius, Metam. 2.21-30; Petronius, Sat. 63; Plato, Respublica 364b–e; Leges 933a–b, e; Tacitus, Ann. 2.27–32, 4.52; CIL VI.19747. The notion that magicians were harmful both to individuals and the state is evident in the regular expulsion of practitioners of magic from Rome, in which magicians found themselves lumped with other subversives and troublemakers perceived to threaten the peace of the city, including Jews, Christians, astrologers, worshippers of Isis, fans of charioteers and pantomime artists. For the expulsion of magicians and others, see Dio Cassius 49.43.5, 52.36.1–2, 57.18.5a, 60.6.6–7; Josephus, A.J. 18.63–64; Philo, De specialibus legibus 159-61; Suetonius, Tib. 36.1, Divus Claudius 25; Tacitus, Ann. 2.85.4–5; Valerius Maximus 1.3.3. See MacMullen, Enemies of the Roman Order, 95–127. Love magic might be thought an exception of a kind, but it was generally considered harmful to the victim. Such magic was believed to be able to drive the object of desire mad (see Plutarch, Mor. 139a; Suetonius, Cal. 50; cf. Jerome, Vita Hilarionis 21; Ovid, Metam. 9.101-238) and that those "dragged together by the magical twisting of threads" were forced into lives contrary to fate (Lucan, Phars. 6.434; see also Apuleius, Metam. 1.5–19, Apol. 41) — not necessarily a happy state of affairs. Those practising it faced severe punishment (Paulus, Sent. 5.23.14). For a comprehensive discussion of love magic, see Christopher A. Faraone, Ancient Greek Love Magic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999). Forms of magic associated with warding off or obtaining relief from sickness might also appear to be an exception. However, we must be careful to note that many practices that might seem, to a modern interpreter, self-evidently magical, were not considered such in antiquity and did not, in most cases, suffer from legal or social prohibitions, something we have noted in our earlier discussion of Cato the Elder's use of an incantation to deal with a dislocation (Agr. 160). For a therapeutic practice to be judged magical it required an additional association with malign forces and nefarious activities and practitioners. This distinction can be seen clearly in Manichaean sources. Although Mani had explicitly prohibited the use of magic in his religion (Kephalaia 6.31.24b–33), Manichaeans had no compunction in using "magical" practices to obtain healing probably because, as Canepa has argued, they did not view activities of a therapeutic kind as proscribed. Matthew P. Canepa, “The Art and Ritual of Manichaean Magic: Text, Object and Image from the Mediterranean to Central Asia,” in Objects in Motion: The Circulation of Religion and Sacred Objects in the Late Antique and Byzantine World, ed. Hallie Meredith, BAR International Series 2247 (Oxford: Archaeopress, 2011), 75. However, cf. Iain Gardner and Samuel N. C. Lieu, eds., “Manichaean Texts from the Roman Empire” (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 278–80. ↵
- For example, the list found in Scott Shauf, Theology as History, History as Theology: Paul in Ephesus in Acts 19, BZNW 133 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2005), 184–88. ↵
- For example, Iamblichus' Babyloniaka in Photius, Bibliotheca 75b (this is not a reference to Iamblichus the Neoplatonist); Lucian, Philops. 11–13; Pseudo-Callisthenes, Alex. 11. ↵
- See, for example, Lucian, Philops. 33–36; Heliodorus. Aeth. 3.16.1–4, 6.12–15. ↵
- See Oliver Phillips, “The Witches’ Thessaly,” in Magic and Ritual in the Ancient World, ed. Paul Allan Mirecki and Marvin W. Meyer, Religions in the Graeco-Roman World 141 (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 378–85. For example, Sosiphanes, Meleager fr. 6 n. 2; Apuleius, Metam. 1.5-19, 2.21; Horace, Epod. 5; Lucan, Phars. 6.434; Plautus, Amphitruo 1043–44; Pliny, Nat. 30.2.6. "Most Romans of the Principate knew Thessaly chiefly through literature as a place of magic and of demonic women." Glen W. Bowersock, “Zur Geschichte des römischen Thessaliens,” Rheinisches Museum 108 (1965): 277. ↵
- See Clinton E. Arnold, Ephesians, Power and Magic: The Concept of Power in Ephesians in Light of Its Historical Setting, SNTSMS 63 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Chester C. McCown, “The Ephesia Grammata in Popular Belief,” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 54 (1923): 128–40, https://doi.org/10.2307/282847. ↵
- For the reputation of Memphis as a key centre for magic, see Apuleius, Metam. 2.28; Jerome, Vit. Hil. 21; Lucian, Philops. 34; Lucan, Phars. 6.459. ↵
- Iamblichus, Babyloniaka in Photius, Bib. 74b; Lucian, Philops. 11-13; Scriptores Historiae Augustae, Macrinus 19. Although often included with various kinds of sorcerer in Roman legislation, Chaldeans were particularly associated with astrology in its most subversive form and were regularly expelled from Rome because of their ability, amongst other things, to ascertain the date of the emperor's death (for example, Tacitus Ann. 12.52). For astrology in antiquity, see Tamsyn Barton, Ancient Astrology (London: Routledge, 1994). It is important to note that by the early Roman Empire "Chaldean" had ceased to have a clear ethnic referent and had become a synonym for a type of seditious magician, a process that had begun in the late Republic. ↵
- For example, Lucian, Philops. 13-15; Porphyry, Vita Pythagorae 28–29. ↵
- For example, Apuleius, Apol. 26; Pliny, Nat. 30.2.3, 30.2.8. ↵
- For example, Apuleius, Metam. 2.28; Heliodorus, Aeth. 3.16; Lucian, Philops. 33–36; Pseudo-Callisthenes, Alex. 1–7, 12. See Robert K. Ritner, “Egyptian Magical Practice under the Roman Empire: The Demotic Spells and Their Religious Context,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II.18.5., ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1995), 3333–79. ↵
- For example, Apuleius, Apol. 90; Origen, Contra Celsum 1.26; Pliny, Nat. 30.2.11. ↵
- The Marsi were an Italian people particularly associated with magic (see Pliny, Nat. 7.2.15; Aulus Gellius, Noctes Atticae 16.11.1). It is often said that ethnic groups associated with magic were "exotic" or "foreign" in the empire and this characteristic played a significant part in the creation of their magical identity. Whilst there is some truth in this, such an evaluation is clearly dependent upon perspective, something which was obviously not uniform: an early imperial Egyptian, for example, was not exotic to another Egyptian, nor were the Marsi, an Italian tribe, particularly exotic to most Romans. For the ethnicity of magicians, see Ogden, Night’s Black Agents, 77–114. ↵
- See especially Jean-Benoît Clerc, Homines magici: étude sur la sorcellerie et la magie dans la société romaine impériale, Publications universitaires européennes. Série III, Histoire et sciences auxiliaires de l’histoire 673 (Bern: Peter Lang, 1995); Christopher A. Faraone, “The Agonistic Context of Early Greek Binding Spells,” in Magika Hiera: Ancient Greek Magic and Religion, ed. Christopher A. Faraone and Dirk Obbink (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 3–32. See also Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 210–26; Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World. The digression in Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.39 is particularly telling in this respect. ↵
- Apuleius, Metam. 3.15; Lucan, Phars. 6.434–506; Pliny, Nat. 28.27.104, 30.5.14; Libanius, Declamationes 41; Pseudo-Quintilian, Decl. mai. 10. ↵
- See, for example, LXX Deut 32.17; 1 Cor 10.20–21; Gal 4.8–11; Justin, 1 Apologia 14. See Flint, “The Demonisation of Magic and Sorcery in Late Antiquity”; Naomi Janowitz, Magic in the Roman World: Pagans, Jews and Christians (London: Routledge, 2001), 16–26. For general prohibitions on magic in Judaism and Christianity see Exod 22.18; Lev 19.26, 31, 20.27; Deut 18.10–11; 1 Sam 28; Mal 3.5; m. Avot 2.7; cf. Philo, Spec. 3.101–2; b. Sanh. 67a; Acts 19.18–20; Gal 5.20; 2 Tim. 3.13; Rev. 9.21, 21.8, 22.15; Didache 2.2, 3.4, 5.1; Barnabas 20.1; Ignatius, Ad Ephesios 19.3; Hippolytus, Traditio Apostolica 16.21, 22. ↵
- Apuleius, Metam. 3.17–18. ↵
- Tacitus, Ann. 2.69. See also Suetonius, Caligula 3.3 and Dio Cassius 57.18.9. ↵
- Apuleius, Metam. 11. ↵
- Apuleius, Metam. 11.1. See Plutarch, De Iside 8. ↵
- See Stavros Frangoulidis, Witches, Isis and Narrative: Approaches to Magic in Apuleius’ “Metamorphoses” (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2008), 5. ↵
- Which, in the case of Frangoulidis, is never stated. ↵
- For discussion of this much-studied text, see Rives, "Magic in Roman Law"; Rives, "Magic, Religion and Law". For another commentary on this law, see Digesta 48.8.2. Cf. also Cicero, Clu. 148. ↵
- The reference to honestiores and humiliores in this text is characteristic of a fundamental distinction between the treatment of different social classes in Roman law. For the classic study of this, see Peter Garnsey, Social Status and Legal Privilege in the Roman Empire (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970). ↵
- Paulus, Sent. 5.23.15–18. The translation is from Rives, “Magic in Roman Law,” 329. ↵
- Apuleius, Apol. 26. A similar distinction is drawn by Philo in Spec. 3.93–103. See Bremmer, “The Birth of the Term ‘Magic.’” ↵
- For oneirology see, for example, Cicero, De divinatione 1.23.46; Dio Cassius, 49.7; Herodotus, 1.107–8, 120, 128, 7.19; Plutarch, Quaestiones convivales 4.5.2. For astrology, see Matt 2.1; Justinus, Epitome Historiarum Trogi Pompeii 1.1.7–10 (although this reputation is probably a result of a popular conflation of ideas about magi and Chaldeans). For other sorts of divination see, for example, Strabo, Geographica 16.2.39. For journeys to the underworld, see Lucian, Men. 6–8, and journeys to the heavens and hell, see Kirdēr's vision. Philippe Gignoux, ed., Quatre inscriptions de Kirdir: textes et concordances, Cahiers de Studia Iranica 9 (Leuven: Peteers, 1991); Shaul Shaked, “Quest and Visionary Journeys in Sasanian Iran,” in Transformations of the Inner Self in Ancient Religions, ed. Jan Assmann and Guy G. Stroumsa (Leiden: Brill, 1999), 65–86. For the cultural representation of magi in Greek and Roman literature, see A. de Jong, Traditions of the Magi: Zoroastrianism in Greek and Latin Literature (Leiden: Brill, 1997), 387–403. See also Michael Becker, “Magoi–Astrologers, Ecstatics, Deceitful Prophets: New Testament Understanding in Jewish and Pagan Context,” in A Kind of Magic: Understanding Magic in the New Testament and Its Religious Environment, ed. Michael Labahn and Bert Jan Lietaert Peerbolte (London: T&T Clark, 2007), 87–106. ↵
- Heliodorus, Aeth. 3.16. ↵
- Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 162. ↵
- Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 7. ↵
- Garth Fowden, The Egyptian Hermes: A Historical Approach to the Late Pagan Mind, 2nd ed. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 162. ↵
- See Graf, Magic in the Ancient World, 232–33. ↵
- For Nigidius Figulus, see Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 170–72. See Apuleius, Apol. 42; Cicero, Timaeus 1.1; Suetonius, Aug. 94. Jerome refers to Nigidius Figulus as a "Pythagoricus et magus". See Jerome, Chronicon Eusebii a Graeco Latine redditumet continuatum 156 H. However, Pythagoreanism did not necessarily have a positive reputation. Cicero, for example, could accuse Vatinius, a self-proclaimed Pythagorean, of practising necromancy and sacrificing young boys (Cicero, Vat. 14). ↵
- See Wilburn, Materia Magica, 264. ↵
- Mary Douglas, “Heathen Darkness,” in Implicit Meanings: Essays in Anthropology (London: Routledge, 1975), 81. ↵
- There is much to gain here from examining the question in the light of cognate discussions about the value of speaking about "religion" in pre-modern cultures. See, for example, the critical analysis of the emergence of "religion" as a historical category in Talal Asad, Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993); Timothy Fitzgerald, The Ideology of Religious Studies, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004). However, cf. Bruce, “Defining Religion.” The interdisciplinary study of "religion" at Çatalhöyük is also helpful for rethinking fundamental assumptions. See Ian Hodder, ed., “Religion in the Emergence of Civilization: Çatalhöyük as a Case Study” (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010). It is common to speak of religion as "embedded" in all aspects of life in the ancient world, as we can see, for example, in Mary Beard, John North, and Simon Price, Religions of Rome: A History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 1:143. However, this raises significant theoretical problems, usefully detailed in Brent Nongbri, “Dislodging ‘Embedded’ Religion: A Brief Note on a Scholarly Trope,” Numen 55 (2008): 440–60. And it cannot be said of magic in antiquity, which seems to have been largely limited to agonistic contexts. ↵
- Homer, Od. 10.133–405 and 569–74. ↵
- Homer, Od. 1.11–9 and 5.151–58. ↵
- Despite allegedly summoning up Odysseus from the dead to gain information about the Trojan war (Philostratus, Heroicus 43) and also being summoned up from the dead himself by the grammarian Apion in order to settle the hotly disputed question of his origins (Pliny, Nat. 30.6.18). ↵
- It could be edited to include even more magic. See, for example, Julius Africanus, Kestoi 18 (PGM XXIII.1–70). ↵
- Pliny, Nat. 30.2.5. ↵
- For example, Apuleius, Metam. 1.5–19, 2.21–30, 3.15–25, 9.29–31; Lucian, Philops. 11–17, 22, 30–31, 33–36; Dial. meretr. 288–89; Men. 2, 6–10, 21–22; Petronius, Sat. 61–63, 131. ↵
- See Graham Anderson, Fairytale in the Ancient World (London: Routledge, 2002), 103. See also Debbie Felton, Haunted Greece and Rome: Ghost Stories from Classical Antiquity (Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, 1999). ↵
- Stein and Stein, The Anthropology of Religion, Magic, and Witchcraft, 172. ↵
- For "moral panics", see Stanley Cohen, Folk Devils and Moral Panics: The Creation of the Mods and the Rockers, 3rd ed. (London: Routledge, 1980). For moral panics, witchcraft and the law, see Erich Goode and Nachman Ben-Yehuda, Moral Panics: The Social Construction of Deviance, 2nd ed. (London: John Wiley & Sons, 2010), 168–96; David Lemmings and Claire Walker, eds., Moral Panics, the Media and the Law in Early Modern England (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009). ↵
- Which seem to have been created, in part, in response to activities ascribed to those involved in the Bacchic "Conspiracy" of 186 BCE. See Livy 39.8–19; ILS 18. ↵
- Geoffrey Pearson, Hooligan: A History of Respectable Fears (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1983), 143. ↵
- The numbers killed in East Anglia probably amounted to a few hundred. James Sharpe, Instruments of Darkness: Witchcraft in Early Modern England (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1997), 126–27. For the context, see Malcolm Gaskill, Witchfinders: A Seventeenth-Century English Tragedy (London: John Murray, 2005). The number of those executed for sorcery in the early Roman empire is difficult to gauge but although we hear about individual trials, such as those of Libo Drusus (Tacitus, Ann. 2.27–32), Claudia Pulchra (Tacitus, Ann. 4.52), Lucius Pituanius and Publius Marcius (Tacitus, Ann. 2.32), Marcia Servilia (Tacitus, Ann. 16.30–33), Apuleius of Madaura (Apol.), and Apollonius of Tyana (Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 8.1–31), these are rare and evidence of the conviction and execution of magicians and witches in any numbers is almost non-existent. For a survey of such trials, see Markéta Melounová, “Trials with Religious and Political Charges from the Principate to the Dominate,” Graeco-Latina Brunensia 17.2 (2012): 117–30. A fourth-century source, Chronographus Anni CCCLIIII, claims that Tiberius put to death 130 sorcerers in his reign, but even if this is reliable it is, according to the source itself, something that was unprecedented. See T. Mommsen, ed., Chronographus Anni CCCLIIII (Berlin: s.n., 1892), 142–48. It is possible that Rome went through its own paroxysms and moral panics brought about by fears of witchcraft but aside from the sensational case of the events surrounding the death of Germanicus (Tacitus, Ann. 2.69; Suetonius. Cal. 3.3; Dio Cassius 57.18.9), which did not result in any executions (Piso and the venefica allegedly committing suicide), there is no evidence of this in the early Roman empire. Our best candidate for such an event, if it is reliable, involves the Republic, and consists of Livy's claim that shortly before the repression of the Bacchic worship in 186 BCE — an extremely unusual event in Roman history — 5,000 people were put to death for veneficia (Livy 39.41 and 40.43). See John A. North, “Religious Toleration in Republican Rome,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 205 (1979): 85–103; Sarolta A. Takács, “Politics and Religion in the Bacchanalian Affair of 186 B.C.E.,” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 100 (2000): 301–10, https://doi.org/10.2307/3185221. We hear of similar panics in the later empire, notably under Constantius II and Valens; see Codex theodosianus 9.16.4–6; Ammianus Marcellinus 19.12, 29.1–2. ↵
- The population of East Anglia was about half a million, out of a total population in England of 5 million. E. A. Wrigley and R. S. Schofield, The Population History of England 1541-1871, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 210. The population of the early Roman empire was about 50 million. Keith Hopkins, “Taxes and Trade in the Roman Empire (200 B.C.-A.D. 400),” Journal of Roman Studies 70 (1980): 118, https://doi.org/10.2307/299558. However, cf. Bruce W. Frier, “More Is Worse: Some Observations on the Population of the Roman Empire,” in Debating Roman Demography, ed. Walter Scheidel (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 139–60. ↵
- Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.34. ↵
- Apuleius, Apol. 26. A point also made by Downing. See Downing, “Magic and Scepticism,” 210. However, Downing does not note that both Apuleius and Apollonius said much the same. ↵
- As Gager, for example, extrapolates from the reference to the use of amulets by Jewish soldiers found in 2 Macc 12.39–40: "To be sure, 2 Maccabees does not offer the sort of hard demographic data preferred by modern social scientists, but the fact remains that in this randomly chosen sample of ancient Jews, every one wore an amulet, as did virtually every sensible person of the time." Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 219. Gager seems to have ignored the rhetorical context. It is just as likely that the claim about the use of amulets is part of an attempt by the author to explain why these particular Jews had died in battle (the amulets are referred to as "idols of Jamnia"; cf. Exod 23.24; 32; Num 25). It tells us more about the theology of the author, and his hostility to idolatry, than the practices of a "randomly chosen sample of Jews". ↵
- Ovid, Am. 1.8.7; Petronius, Sat. 131; Virgil, Ecl. 8.74–77. ↵
- Amongst the plethora of jewellery found there were a number of charms but none of these contained elements that Romans would have categorized as magical. The only possible exceptions are those that took the form of representations of Fascinus, the divine, and often winged, phallus, the medicus invidiae which was thought to protect against the evil eye (Pliny, Nat. 28.7.39). However, Fascinus was a public cult, most famously venerated by the Vestal Virgins, and representations of Fascinus functioned as a general apotropaic image, protecting from harm of any kind, and especially that which resulted from envy. It was not in itself considered magical nor necessarily indicated anxiety about the possible presence of magic. ↵
- See Fergus Millar, “Epigraphy,” in Sources for Ancient History, ed. Michael Crawford (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 91. The graffiti from Pompeii is overwhelmingly scatological or erotic. See, for example, CIL VI.1679, 1751, 3932, 3951, 4523, 5092, 7716, 8442, 8767, 8898, 10070, 10488, 10619, 10675, 10677, 10678. There is nothing magical about the so-called "Magical Squares" found in Pompeii (CIL VI. 8297, 8623). For the graffiti, see Helen Henrietta Tanzer, The Common People of Pompeii: A Study of the Graffiti (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press, 1939). Cf. also Jennifer A. Baird and Claire Taylor, eds., Ancient Graffiti in Context (Abingdon: Routledge, 2011); Antonio Varone, Erotica Pompeiana: Love Inscriptions on the Walls of Pompeii (Rome: L’Erma di Bretschneider, 2002). Likewise, there is nothing magical about the so-called "House of the Magical Rites", and it appears to have been so named because of the presence of two hands of Sabazios, the Phrygian and Thracian sky-god. To refer to such objects as "magical" is to engage in the error of "Classicity" and to confuse these objects with the so-called "Hand of Glory" of later witchcraft traditions. See Mastrocinque, Kronos, Shiva, and Asklepios, 4; Albert H. Tricomi, “The Severed Hand in Webster’s Duchess of Malfi,” SEL Studies in English Literature 1500-1900 44.2 (2004): 347–58, https://doi.org/10.1353/sel.2004.0023. ↵
- Wilburn, Materia Magica, 15. ↵
- Wilburn, Materia Magica, 20. Wilburn explains this dearth of archaeological evidence as a result of "the vagaries of preservation, a desire for secrecy on the part of the practitioner, and the tendency of rituals to destroy or use up the material components of a spell." Wilburn, Materia Magica, 25. Whilst these factors no doubt affected the record, they do not account for it. He seems unwilling to accept that the lack of evidence might well be an indication that magic was, in fact, not widely practised. ↵
- Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 219. ↵
- For the invisibility amulet see Cyranides, 1.15.33–37. Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 115. See also the invisibility lotion found in PGM I.222–31 and the famous ring of Gyges in Plato, Rep. 359d–60b. For a discussion of invisibility spells, see Paul A. Mirecki, “Manichaean Allusions to Ritual and Magic: Spells for Invisibility in the Coptic Kephalaia,” in The Light and the Darkness: Studies in Manichaeism and Its World, ed. Paul Mirecki and Jason BeDuhn (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 173–80. ↵
- For an amulet promising relief from migraine, see Cyranides, 1.16.38–42. Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 119. For an amulet promising relief from indigestion, see Cyranides 1.9.12–16. Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 71. For an amulet promising to prevent drunkenness, see Cyranides, 1.8.25–28. Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 65. For amulets promising to make the wearer popular and lucky, see Cyranides, 1.5.27–31 and 1.4.45–61. Waegeman, Amulet and Alphabet, 41, 35. See also PGM XIV.309–334. ↵
- See Faraone, Ancient Greek Love Magic, 85; David Jordan, “A Survey of Greek Defixiones Not Included in the Special Corpora,” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 26.2 (1985): 151–97. I would like to thank Andrew Wilson for drawing my attention to this defixio. ↵
- Paul Roberts, Life and Death in Pompeii and Herculaneum (London: British Museum Press, 2013), 290–91. ↵
- The charms were made of a variety of different materials that originated from all over the empire and beyond. Roberts, Life and Death in Pompeii and Herculaneum, 291. ↵
- See, for example, the discussions in Jean Baudrillard, “The System of Collecting,” in The Cultures of Collecting, ed. John Elsner and Roger Cardinal (London: Reaktion, 1994), 7–24; Fiona Parrott, “Death, Memory and Collecting: Creating the Conditions for Ancestralisation in South London Households,” in Unpacking the Collection, ed. Sarah Byrne et al. (New York, NY: Springer, 2011), 289–305. ↵
- Ian Woodward, Understanding Material Culture (London: Sage, 2007), vi. ↵
- Hildred Geertz, “An Anthropology of Religion and Magic, I,” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 6.1 (1975): 83. ↵
- Arjun Appadurai, ed., The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). ↵
- Igor Kopytoff, “The Cultural Biography of Things: Commoditization as Process,” in The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural Perspective, ed. Arjun Appadurai (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 64–94. ↵
- Woodward, Understanding Material Culture, 4. ↵
- For example, Plutarch, Vitae Parallelae, Pericles. 38. Cf. Diogenes Laertius 10. ↵
- See, for example, Soranus, Gyn. 3.42. Galen's position seems somewhat more complex. He was generally dismissive of amulets. Nutton, Ancient Medicine, 268–70. However, he did allow for the possibility that some might have an effect by virtue of the materials used, though carving amulets into particular shapes was, in his judgement, pointless. Nutton, Ancient Medicine, 269. See also P. T. Keyser, “Science and Magic in Galen’s Recipes (Sympathy and Efficacy),” in «Docente natura». Mélanges de médicine ancienne et médiévale offerts à Guy Sabbah, ed. Armelle Debru and Nicoletta Palmieri (St Etienne: Université de St Etienne, 2001), 175–98. For an example of Galen conceding that an amulet could work, despite his scepticism, see De simplicium medicamentorum 6.3.10. For the opinion of other medical writers about amulets, see the useful collection of sources in Eugene Tavenner, Studies in Magic from Latin Literature (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1916), 76–123. ↵
- As Graf has noted, a magical "explanation of an untimely death is relatively rare and late". Graf, “Untimely Death, Witchcraft, and Divine Vengeance,” 139. ↵
- Indeed, Parsons has even suggested, in his study of the documentary data from Oxyrhynchus, that what limited evidence we have of the use of magic appears to come from a small, privileged section of society and reflect their preoccupations; "the diversion of well-heeled, sex-crazed urbanites". Peter John Parsons, City of the Sharp-Nosed Fish: Greek Lives in Roman Egypt (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2007), 192. ↵
- The study of popular culture in modern and early modern societies is long established. See, for example, Peter Burke, Popular Culture in Early Modern Europe (London: Temple Smith, 1978); Morag Shiach, Discourse on Popular Culture: Class, Gender and History in Cultural Analysis, 1730 to the Present (Cambridge: Polity, 1989). However, interest in the popular culture of the Roman empire is less so. For recent contributions, see John R. Clarke, Art in the Lives of Ordinary Romans: Visual Representation and Non-Elite Viewers in Italy, 100 B.C.-A.D. 315, 2nd ed. (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2006); Nicholas Horsfall, The Culture of the Roman Plebs (London: Duckworth, 2003); Robert C. Knapp, Invisible Romans: Prostitutes, Outlaws, Slaves, Gladiators, Ordinary Men and Women the Romans That History Forgot (London: Profile Books, 2011); Teresa Morgan, Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Jeremy Peter Toner, Popular Culture in Ancient Rome (Cambridge: Polity, 2009). See also Justin J. Meggitt, Paul, Poverty and Survival (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1998); Meggitt, “Sources: Use, Abuse and Neglect: The Importance of Ancient Popular Culture.,” in Christianity at Corinth: The Scholarly Quest for the Corinthian Church, ed. David G. Horrell and Edward Adams (London: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004), 241–53. ↵
- Such as Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts; Georg Luck, Arcana Mundi: Magic and the Occult in the Greek and Roman Worlds: A Collection of Ancient Texts, 2nd ed. (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006). ↵
- See the analysis of such literature found in Morgan, Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire. Of course, in an empire with limited literacy, in which no more than about 20% of males could read, this is not the same as saying that the texts themselves were necessarily widely read, but their contents were widely known and can be judged to be indicative of wider culture. For the figure of around 20%, see Morgan, Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire, 3. ↵
- See Teresa Morgan, “Divine-Human Relations in the Aesopic Corpus,” Journal of Ancient History 1.1 (2013): 3–4. See also Christos A. Zafiropoulos, Ethics in Aesop’s Fables: The Augustana Collection (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 36–41. For the cultural significance of Aesop, see especially Leslie Kurke, Aesopic Conversations Popular Tradition, Cultural Dialogue, and the Invention of Greek Prose (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011). Aesop's Fabulae were popular in the first-century CE, as we can see in the Latin edition by Phaedrus and the Greek editions by Babrius and the anonymous compiler of the Collectio Augustana. See Zafiropoulos, Ethics in Aesop’s Fables, 23. See also Papyri Graecae Haunienses 3.46. Although the fables ascribed to Aesop originated in the fourth century BCE, the versions popular in the early Roman empire reflected and contributed to cultural assumptions of this later period. For fabular literature in the early Roman empire, see Francisco Rodríguez Adrados, History of the Graeco-Latin Fable: The Fable during the Roman Empire and in the Middle Ages, vol. 2 (Leiden: Brill, 2000). Such material has been widely neglected as a source for cultural, social and religious history. See, for example, H. S. Versnel, Coping with the Gods (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 327. ↵
- Aesop, Fab. 56. For this fable, see Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 151–52; Ben E. Perry, ed., Babrius and Phaedrus (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965), 430–31. ↵
- See William F. Hansen, ed., Anthology of Ancient Greek Popular Literature (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1998), 106–62; Niklas Holzberg, The Ancient Fable: An Introduction (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2002), 72–84. For an exception, cf. Vit. Aesop. 16. ↵
- See Tavenner, Studies in Magic from Latin Literature, 54. This is perhaps all the more surprising as Valerius Maximus' work reveals an intense religiosity. He was not averse to detailing prodigies and wonders (for example, Valerius Maximus 1.6) and he evidently wrote for the "religiously credulous". Hans Friedrich Mueller, Roman Religion in Valerius Maximus (London: Routledge, 2002), 53. ↵
- For Phlegon of Tralles, see William F. Hansen, ed., Phlegon of Tralles’ Book of Marvels, trans. William F. Hansen (Exeter: Exeter University Press, 1996). For paradoxography, see Guido Schepens, “Ancient Paradoxography: Origin, Evolution, Production and Reception. Part I. The Hellenistic Period,” in La letteratura di consumo nel mondo greco-latino. Atti del convegno internazionale, Cassino, 14-17 settembre 1994, ed. Oronzo Pecere and Antonio Stramaglia (Cassino: Università degli Studi di Cassino, 1996), 375–409; Kris Delcroix, “Ancient Paradoxography: Origin, Evolution, Production and Reception. Part II. The Roman Period,” in La letteratura di consumo nel mondo greco-latino. Atti del convegno internazionale, Cassino, 14–17 settembre 1994, ed. Oronzo Pecere and Antonio Stramaglia (Cassino: Università degli studi di Cassino, 1996), 410–60. ↵
- For Artemidorus' method, which involved both the critical use of pre-existing texts and interviews, see Oneirocritica 1.1. For a positive assessment of Artemidorus as an ethnographer of antiquity, see John J. Winkler, The Constraints of Desire: The Anthropology of Sex and Gender in Ancient Greece (London: Routledge, 1990), 26. However, cf. William V. Harris, Dreams and Experience in Classical Antiquity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009), 113–15. See also Daniel E. Harris-McCoy, ed., Artemidorus’ Oneirocritica: Text, Translation, and Commentary (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012); Robert J. White, ed., The Interpretation of Dreams. Oneirocritica by Artemidorus (Park Ridge, NJ: Noyes, 1975). ↵
- For example, Artemidorus, Oneir. 1.5; 3.22, 3.47, 3.51, 4.2, 45. ↵
- For example, Artemidorus, Oneir. 4.18, 5.88. ↵
- Artemidorus, Oneir. 1.79. ↵
- Artemidorus, Oneir. 2.53, 4.33, 4.49. ↵
- Artemidorus, Oneir. 3.24. ↵
- Artemidorus, Oneir. 2.69 does include a single mention of necromancers. ↵
- For the Philogelos and its cultural significance, see Barry Baldwin, ed., The Philogelos, or, Laughter-Lover, London Studies in Classical Philology 10 (Amsterdam: J. C. Gieben, 1983); Baldwin, Roman and Byzantine Papers (Amsterdam: J. C. Gieben, 1989), 624–37; Roger D. Dawe, ed., “Philogelos” (Leipzig: Teubner, 2000); Hansen, Anthology of Ancient Greek Popular Literature, 272–82. For references to the use of joke books, see Athenaeus, 614d–e; Plautus, Persa 392–94; Stichus 454–55. ↵
- Gerald M. Browne, ed., Sortes Astrampsychi. Volumen I. Ecdosis Prior. (Leipzig: Teubner, 1983); Hansen, Anthology of Ancient Greek Popular Literature, 285–324; F. A. J. Hoogendijk and W. Clarysse, “De Sortes van Astrampsychus,” Kleio 11 (1981): 53–99; Randy Stewart, ed., Sortes Astrampsychi. Volume II, Ecdosis Altera (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2001). See also P. W. van der Horst, “Sortes: Sacred Books as Instant Oracles in Late Antiquity,” in The Use of Sacred Books in the Ancient World, ed. Leonard Victor Rutgers (Leuven: Peeters, 1998), 143–74. ↵
- Diogenes Laertius 1.2. ↵
- The closest we find to a concern about magic is one question about poisoning (Sortes Astrampsychi Q. 91, cf. R. 9.8). See P.Oxy. 12.1477; Gager, Curse Tablets and Binding Spells from the Ancient World, 220. For the use of such do-it-yourself oracles, see Pausanias 7.25.10. ↵
- The answer was obtained by throwing dice to determine which verse was applicable. For the Homeromanteion, see Derek Collins, “The Magic of Homeric Verses,” Classical Philology 103.3 (2008): 211–36, https://doi.org/10.1086/596515; Franco Maltomimi, “P. Lond. 121 (=PGM VII) 1-221: Homeromanteion,” Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 106 (1995): 107–22; Parsons, City of the Sharp-Nosed Fish: Greek Lives in Roman Egypt, 189–90; Gregg Schwendner, “Under Homer’s Spell,” in Magic and Divination in the Ancient World, ed. Leda Jean Ciraolo and Jonathan Lee Seidel (Leiden: Brill, 2002), 107–18. Versions of this oracle can be found in P.Oxy. 56.3831; PGM VII.1–148; P.Bon. 1.3. ↵
- Betz, The Greek Magical Papyri, xli. ↵
- Although the analysis of secularism and atheism are long established in the study of religion, "non-religion" has only recently become a focus of considerable attention. See, especially, the work of the Nonreligion and Secularity Research Network, which, though influenced by the seminal text of Colin Campbell, first published in 1971, has just been initiated. See Colin Campbell, Toward a Sociology of Irreligion: New Perspectives in Sociology (London: Macmillan, 1971). Religious indifference and "non-religion" are not identical, the latter is usually taken to imply "a relationship of difference to religion". Lois Lee, “Research Note: Talking about a Revolution: Terminology for the New Field of Non-Religion Studies,” Journal of Contemporary Religion 27.1 (2012): 131. So far "non-religion" has only been scrutinised in relation to modernity, but there are significant commonalities with the ancient world. It is possible that the reluctance to examine religious indifference in antiquity owes itself, in part, to an understandable reaction to earlier, prejudicial and pejorative constructions of Roman religion as something that had "failed", an interpretative trope common in, for example, in past histories of the origins of Christianity that tried to explain its "success". See, for example, W. H. C Frend, The Rise of Christianity (London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1984), 904. ↵
- Downing does not draw such a distinction which makes his resulting analysis problematic. See Downing, “Magic and Scepticism.” ↵
- See R. J Hankinson, The Sceptics, 2nd ed. (London: Routledge, 1998). A school that would see a revival in the late second century CE with Sextus Empiricus. See Alan Bailey, Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002); Richard Bett, Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003). ↵
- Although it was a common trope in anti-magical writing to complain that its practitioners functionally denied the existence of the gods because of the power they claimed over them (Hippocrates, Morb. Sacr. 3.20; Lucan, Phars. 6.523; Plato, Leg. 909a), gods, albeit primarily chthonic ones, were central to magical rites. ↵
- See, for example, the complaint of Jason P. Davies, Rome’s Religious History: Livy, Tacitus and Ammianus on Their Gods (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 17. ↵
- See Denis C. Feeney, Literature and Religion at Rome: Cultures, Contexts, and Beliefs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 12. See also Meredith B. McGuire, Lived Religion: Faith and Practice in Everyday Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 39. ↵
- Ken Dowden, Religion and the Romans (London: Bristol Classical Press, 1992), 8. ↵
- Feeney, Literature and Religion at Rome, 14. ↵
- Paul Veyne, Did the Greeks Believe in Their Myths?: An Essay on the Constitutive Imagination, trans. Paula Wissing (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 41–57. For all the analytical value of this phrase, it is an uncomfortable one in its essentialist assumptions about the cultures and nations that constitute the Balkans. ↵
- See Feeney, Literature and Religion at Rome, 12–46; Carin M. C. Green, “Varro’s Three Theologies and Their Influence on the Fasti,” in Ovid’s Fasti, ed. Geraldine Herbert-Brown (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 71–100. ↵
- Though cf. Sylloge Inscriptionum Graecarum 1168.29–33 and the case of "Apistos" at the Asclepeion at Epidauros. Healing cults, such as that of Asclepius, may have been the exception to this rule. ↵
- Even if in magic, this power was often conceptualised as something at the beck and call of the magician. See Apuleius, Metam. 3.15; Lucan, Phars. 6.434–506; Pliny, Nat. 28.27.104; Libanius, Decl. 41; Pseudo-Quintilian, Decl. mai. 10. Some perceived that such power did not originate with the gods but demonic or ghostly forces (for example, Apuleius, Apol. 43). The control of demons and ghosts was a recurring theme in magical and anti-magical literature. See, for example, PGM XIa.1-40; Apuleius, Metam. 1.10, 9.29–31; Eusebius, C. Hier. 27; Ps-Quintilian, Decl. mai. 19. It should be noted that demons and ghosts were generally closely related in the early imperial period, though not in Judaism and Christianity; see Apuleius, De deo Socr. 15; Pausanias 1.32.4–5; Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 3.38; Tertullian, An. 57. ↵
- For a helpful discussion of the different conceptions of belief in the critical study of religion, see Martin D. Stringer, Contemporary Western Ethnography and the Definition of Religion (London: Continuum, 2008), 39–46. ↵
- There have been some innovative studies of the social world of philosophers in the early Roman empire, such as Kendra Eshleman, The Social World of Intellectuals in the Roman Empire: Sophists, Philosophers, and Christians (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012). However, there has been little analysis of their relative significance within society as whole, and which of their ideas, if any, might have been "popular", with the occasional, notable, exception, such as Abraham Malherbe, Paul and the Popular Philosophers (Minneapolis, MN: Augsburg Fortress, 1989). For philosophical commitments in the Graeco-Roman world, see David Sedley, “Philosophical Allegiance in the Greco-Roman World,” in Philosophia Togata: Essays on Philosophy and Roman Society, ed. Miriam T. Griffin and Jonathan Barnes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), 97–119. ↵
- Martin Ferguson Smith, The Philosophical Inscription of Diogenes of Oinoanda, Ergänzungsbände zu den Tituli Asiae Minoris 20 (Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1996); Smith, Supplement to Diogenes of Oinoanda: The Epicurean Inscription, Scuola di Epicuro. Supplemento 3 (Napoli: Bibliopolis, 2003). ↵
- For Cynics see Luis E. Navia, Classical Cynicism: A Critical Study (Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger, 1996); Navia, Diogenes the Cynic: The War against the World (Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 2005). Despite the plethora of scholarly literature on Cynicism, Aune is right to note that they are often overlooked in surveys of Hellenistic philosophy. See David E. Aune, “The Problem of the Passions in Cynicism,” in Passions and Moral Progress in Greco-Roman Thought, ed. John T. Fitzgerald (New York, NY: Routledge, 2008), 48–49; Navia, ed., The Philosophy of Cynicism: An Annotated Bibliography (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1995). ↵
- Though see Horsfall, The Culture of the Roman Plebs, 54–55. The popularity of the Epicurean epitaph "Non fui, fui, non sum, non curo" ("I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care") may be indicative of the wider impact of that school. ↵
- See Polybius 16.12; cf. also 3.48. See, for an example from the early Roman empire, Tacitus, Hist. 1.86, although Tacitus too could on occasion demonstrate this failing. See Ronald Syme, Tacitus (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1958), 521–26. See also Lucian, Quomodo historia conscribenda sit; Vera historia and J. R. Morgan, “Lucian’s True Histories and the Wonders beyond Thule of Antonius Diogenes,” Classical Quarterly 35.2 (1985): 475–90, https://doi.org/10.2307/639077. For the irrelevance of the supernatural (though not necessarily the divine) in theories of historical causation following Thucydides, see Charles W. Fornara, The Nature of History in Ancient Greece and Rome (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1988), 81. For a low estimation of the credulity of many historians from the early Roman empire, see Seneca, Naturales quaestiones 7.16. ↵
- Jason Davies, “Religion in Historiography,” in The Cambridge Companion to the Roman Historians, ed. Andrew Feldherr (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 168. Dionysius of Halicarnassus' Antiquitates Romanae provides an excellent example of this. Dionysus' rational approach to myth is so thoroughgoing that it has been called "euhemeristic". Matthew Fox, “History and Rhetoric in Dionysius of Halicarnassus,” Journal of Roman Studies 83 (1993): 44, https://doi.org/10.2307/300977. However, this may well be a rhetorical move common to many authors, and an aspect of authorial persona. Jörg Rüpke, Religion of the Romans, trans. Richard Gordon (Cambridge: Polity, 2007), 139. ↵
- See, for example, Diodorus Siculus 4.47.3–4. Even a writer such as Livy, who provides a list of prodigies for each year of Roman history, is undecided about both the origins and meanings of many of these, and critical of the credulity of those who generated such stories (for example, Livy 24.10.6). For an example of such ambivalence, see Josephus, A.J. 1.108, 3.81, 3.322, 4.158, 10.281, 17.354. ↵
- Dio Cassius, for example, could recount dreams and signs that were taken by Septimus Severus as an indication that he would become emperor (73.23.1) whilst complaining that many stories about miraculous events are no more than the result of "idle talk and fear" (14.57.7). Robert M. Grant, Miracle and Natural Law in Graeco-Roman and Early Christian Thought (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1952), 171. ↵
- See, for example, Hippocrates, Morb. Sacr. 1. It is important to note that the disease was still considered "sacred" by the writer of this treatise. As Eijk has demonstrated, the author does not reject the divine character of the disease, but modifies the sense in which this disease (and, indeed, all diseases), may be regarded as divine: it was divine not because it had been sent by a god, but because it shares in the divine character of nature in showing a fixed pattern of cause and effect and in being subordinated to a natural "law" or regularity. Philip J. van der Eijk, Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity: Doctors and Philosophers on Nature, Soul, Health and Disease (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 45. See also Owsei Temkin, The Falling Sickness: A History of Epilepsy from the Greeks to the Beginnings of Modern Neurology., 2nd ed. (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1971). For the rationalism of the Hippocratic corpus, see Jacques Jouanna, Hippocrates, trans. Malcolm B. DeBevoise (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999), 181–209. Interestingly the author of De morbo sacro saw the claims of magic as the denial and negation of the power of the gods. See Hippocrates, Morb. Sacr. 3.20. Cf. Lucan, Phars. 6.492–94. ↵
- Galen, De libris propriis 2.19.18, 4; De Praegnotione ad Epigenem 2.12; De methodo medendi 9.4. However, Harris maintains that Galen, like many in the empire, had become uncomfortable about such epiphanic dreams and they did "not suit the image of himself he was keen on maintaining". Harris, Dreams and Experience in Classical Antiquity, 64. For Galen's religious beliefs, see Fridolf Kudlien, “Galen’s Religious Beliefs,” in Galen: Problems and Prospects, ed. Vivian Nutton (London: Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, 1981), 117–30. See also Mark Holowchak, “Interpreting Dreams for Corrective Regimen: Diagnostic Dreams in Greco-Roman Medicine,” Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences 56.4 (2001): 169–79; Steven M. Oberhelman, “Dreams in Graeco-Roman Medicine,” in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. II.37.1, ed. W. Haase (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1993), 127–36. For the relationship between secular and sacred in Greek medicine, see Herman F. J. Horstmanshoff, “‘Did the God Learn Medicine?’ Asclepius and Temple Medicine in Aelius Aristides’ Sacred Tales,” in Magic and Rationality in Ancient Near Eastern and Graeco-Roman Medicine, ed. Herman F. J. Horstmanshoff and Marten Stol (Leiden: Brill, 2004), 325–42; Ido Israelowich, Society, Medicine, and Religion in the Sacred Tales of Aelius Aristides (Leiden: Brill, 2012); G. E. R. Lloyd, In the Grip of Disease: Studies in the Greek Imagination (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 40–83. ↵
- For the different therapeutic approaches used in the Roman empire see, for example, Audrey Cruse, Roman Medicine (Stroud: Tempus, 2004); Ralph Jackson, Doctors and Diseases in the Roman Empire (London: British Museum Press, 1993); Vivian Nutton, “Healers in the Medical Marketplace: Towards a Social History of Graeco-Roman Medicine,” in Medicine in Society: Historical Essays, ed. Andrew Wear (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 15–58. ↵
- The famous incident in which Asclepiades of Bithynia, the physician credited with bringing Greek medicine to Rome, restored a man already on his funeral bier — by observing the presence of his vital signs and administering drugs — is emblematic of such a naturalistic approach to medicine. See Apuleius, Florida 19; Pliny, Nat. 7.37.124; Celsus, De medicina 2.6.15;. Cf. Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 4.45; Luke 7.11-17. ↵
- The continuing significance of writings by the likes of Euhemerus, Palaephatus, Xenophanes, and Zoilus, which encouraged the rational explanation of myth, no doubt contributed to such a culture. For Euhemerus, see Marek Winiarczyk, Euhemeros von Messene: Leben, Werk und Nachwirkung (München: Saur, 2002); Marek Winiarczyk, The “Sacred History” of Euhemerus of Messene (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2013). For Palaephatus, see Jacob Stern, ed., Palaephatus: Peri Apiston (on Unbelievable Tales) (Wauconda: Bolchazy-Carducci, 1996). For Xenophanes, see James Lesher, ed., Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments. A Text and Translation with a Commentary (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001). For Zoilus, see Henrietta V. Apfel, “Homeric Criticism in the Fourth Century B.C.,” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 69 (1938): 245–58, https://doi.org/10.2307/283178. For the Homeromastix tradition more generally, of which Zoilus is the most famous figure, see J. T. Katridis, “A Cynic Homeromastix,” in Serta Turyniana: Studies in Greek Literature and Palaeography in Honor of Alexander Turyn, ed. John L. Heller and J. K. Newman (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1974), 361–73. The persistence of knowledge of such writers is evident from Christian apologetic literature, which often made use of their criticisms. See, for example, Darryl W. Palmer, “Atheism, Apologetic, and Negative Theology in the Greek Apologists of the Second Century,” Vigiliae Christianae 37.3 (1983): 234–59. ↵
- See Athenagoras, Legatio pro Christianis 4 (I would like to thank Richard Carrier for this reference). See also Cicero, Nat. d. 3. 37, 89 for similar traditions. For Diagoras, see Leonard Woodbury, “The Date and Atheism of Diagoras of Melos,” Phoenix 19.3 (1965): 178–211, https://doi.org/10.2307/1086282. For atheism in antiquity, see Jan N. Bremmer, “Atheism in Antiquity,” in The Cambridge Companion to Atheism, ed. Michael Martin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 11–26. However, it is probably more appropriate to call such figures adevists rather than atheists, to use the term initially employed by Max Müller to refer to those who denied the gods rather than the divine per se. See James Thrower, Western Atheism: A Short History (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1971), 17. See also Thrower, The Alternative Tradition : Religion and the Rejection of Religion in the Ancient World, Religion and Society (Hague, Netherlands) 18 (The Hague: Mouton, 1980). ↵
- See Suetonius, Tib. 2.6. ↵
- For example, Julius Caesar, and indeed the whole Senate ignored adverse omens when he sought approval for a new agrarian law. See Suetonius. Divus Julius 20.1. ↵
- Suetonius, Cal. 5.1. ↵
- Some even excised them entirely from Homer. See James J. O’Hara, “Fragment of a Homer-Hypothesis with No Gods,” Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 56 (1984): 1–9, https://doi.org/10.2307/20184046. ↵
- The kind of reaction found in Thucydides' account of the plague in Athens (2.53). See also Lucretius 6.1272–1286. ↵
- P.Ryl. 3.493. See also Aesop, Fab. 119; Perry, Babrius and Phaedrus, 155. ↵
- Arrian, Epictetus Enchridion 31. ↵
- See, for example, Lucian, Juppiter confutatus, Juppiter tragoedus, Deorm concilium and Alexander (Pseudomantis), or Seneca, Apocolocyntosis. ↵
- See, for example, the libidinous and sacrilegious graffito from Catania in Sicily discussed in G. Manganaro, “Graffiti e iscrizioni funerarie della Sicilia orientale,” Helikon 2 (1962): 490–93. See also Lionel Casson, Travel in the Ancient World (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), 216–17. ↵
- The most famous attack on the oracles in antiquity was The Detection of Impostors of Oenomaus of Gadara, a Cynic who lived during the reign of Hadrian. Significant extracts from his work appear in Eusebius, Praeparatio evangelica 5.18–36 (cf. his remarks on fate in 6.7). Oenomaus was criticised by Julian for his damaging effect on belief in the gods. See Julian, Orationes 7.209 (cf. 6.199). See also Jürgen Hammerstaedt, Die Orakelkritik des Kynikers Oenomaus (Frankfurt am Main: Athenäum, 1988). Oenomaus gained a reputation for being the most learned pagan philosopher amongst Jews. See Genesis Rabbah 65.20; Louis H. Feldman, Jewish Life and Thought among Greeks and Romans: Primary Readings (London: Continuum, 1996), 130. ↵
- For example, Valerius Maximus 1.1.19. ↵
- For example, Tacitus, Ann. 2.69. ↵
- See, for example, the actions under Tiberius (Josephus, A.J. 18.4; Suetonius, Tib. 36.1). See also Dio Cassius 59.28; Suetonius, Cal. 22. Cf. also Josephus, A.J. 18.257–305; Philo, Legat. 134. Of course, the introduction of Isis worship into Rome was not straightforward, and such actions might be viewed as a response to a foreign cult that had not, unlike, for example, the cult of Cycbele, been formally established in the city (Cybele arrived in Rome in 204 BCE on the orders of the Senate, in response to a Sibylline oracle [Livy 29.10–14]; see Mary Beard, “The Roman and the Foreign: The Cult of the ‘Great Mother’ in Imperial Rome,” in Shamanism, History, and the State, ed. Nicholas Thomas and Caroline Humphrey (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1994), 164–90. However, such behaviour does show a disregard for the power of a god, one that was venerated throughout the empire, and reveals implicit assumptions about human primacy. Despite a cultural concern with antiquity and continuity, cults were regularly superseded, dissolved, abandoned, and sometimes abolished in a process of the focalisation and defocalisation of specific deities in Roman life. See Michael Lipka, Roman Gods: A Conceptual Approach (Leiden: Brill, 2009). ↵
- Most famously Augustus, who, dressed as Apollo, oversaw a scandalous dinner party of twelve other "gods". See, Suetonius, Aug. 70. ↵
- Kathleen M. Coleman, “Fatal Charades: Roman Executions Staged as Mythological Enactments,” Journal of Roman Studies 80 (1990): 44–73, https://doi.org/10.2307/300280. ↵
- Scheid, An Introduction to Roman Religion, 26–27. In particular by theft or neglect of their property. ↵
- Scheid, An Introduction to Roman Religion, 28. ↵
- On impiety, see Mario Torelli, ed., Le Délit religieux dans la cité antique: table ronde : Rome, 6-7 avril 1978, Collection de l’école Française de Rome 48 (Roma: Ecole française de Rome, 1981). ↵
- CIL VI.27365. The epitaph asked those reading it, if they had any doubts about the existence of ghosts, to call out to the dead person. The joke relied on a local echo. See Ogden, Greek and Roman Necromancy, 6. ↵
- Marcus Aurelius, Meditationes 1.6. ↵
- Cicero, Nat. d. 2.5. ↵
- Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 210. It should be noted that this section is indebted to Gordon's ground-breaking treatment of the subject. See Gordon Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 210–43. ↵
- Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 210. ↵
- Ogden, Magic, Witchcraft, and Ghosts, 177. ↵
- Aesop, Fab. 56. For this fable, see Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 150–52; Perry, Babrius and Phaedrus, 430–31. ↵
- See, for example, Ennius, Telamo frg. 134b. This is quoted in Cicero, Div. 1.132. However, see Alex Nice, “‘Ennius or Cicero?’ The Disreputable Diviners at Cicero, de Divinatione 1.132,” Acta Classica 44 (2001): 153–66. For Ennius, see Henry D. Jocelyn, The Tragedies of Ennius (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967). ↵
- Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 213. See, for example, Tibullus, Eleg. 1.8.24f; Propertius 2.4; Ovid, Amores 2.99–106, Remedia amoris 261–290; Nemesianus, Eclogae 2.62–73. ↵
- Ovid, Her. 12.163–167. See also Deianeira in Pseudo-Seneca, Hercules Oetaeus 465–72. See also Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.39. ↵
- See Cicero, Nat. d. 3.12; cf. Horace, Sat. 2.6.77f. Such a topos was an old one and can be found in the fourth-century BCE comedy of Anaxilas, Lyre-Maker fr. 18. See John M. Edmonds, ed., The Fragments of Attic Comedy, 2 vols. (Leiden: Brill, 1957), 336–39. Cf. Origen, Cels. 3.59 for similar remarks by Celsus about the categories of people drawn to Christianity. ↵
- Tacitus, Ann. 16.30-33. ↵
- Galen, De simplicium medicamentorum 6. See Véronique Boudon, “Aux marges de la médecine rationnelle: médecins et charlatans à Rome au temps de Galien,” Revue des études grecques 116 (2003): 109–31. ↵
- Pliny, Nat. 30.5.14–15. See also Suetonius, Nero 34.4. Pliny did, however, note that "if there is a shimmer of truth in it, that shimmer owes more to chemistry than magic." (Nat. 30.6.17). ↵
- Lucian, Demonax 23. See also the joke in Apuleius, Metam. 3.23. ↵
- See, for example, Pliny, Nat. 25.5.10. For the "Thessalian trick" see Apollonius Rhodius, Argonautica 4.60. See also Livy 44.37 for a different use of knowledge of an eclipse. ↵
- Plutarch, Mor. 145d. Cf. 416f–147a. ↵
- Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.39. See, for example, Lucian, Alex. 21 for a reference to such a work. ↵
- For example, the theory of effluences proposed by Empedocles and Democritus allowed them to explain magical phenomena as in accord with natural laws. See Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 221–22. ↵
- Hippolytus, Refutatio omnium haeresium 4.28–42. As Gordon has noted, Hippolytus' remarks appear to be dependent upon a Cynic source as they are "founded on the Cynic contrast between reason and folly". Gordon, “Imagining Greek and Roman Magic,” 218. Dickie claims that Hippolytus' source is a lost text called The Art of Thrasymedes. Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 219. Early Christian attacks on magic more often presuppose that it made use of supernatural but malign power, as we can see, for example, in Tertullian, Apologeticus 1.23. ↵
- See Peter Lamont, Extraordinary Beliefs: A Historical Approach to a Psychological Problem (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 34–43. ↵
- Hippolytus, Haer. 4.41. See Lucian, Alex. 26. ↵
- Hippolytus, Haer. 4.32. For accounts of mechanical devices intended to create such special effects, see Steven J. Scherrer, “Signs and Wonders in the Imperial Cult: A New Look at a Roman Religious Institution in the Light of Rev 13:13-15,” Journal of Biblical Literature 103.4 (1984): 599–610, https://doi.org/10.2307/3260470. ↵
- See PGM VII.167-86. See also PGM XIb, VII.149-54. SeeDavid Bain, “Salpe’s ΠΑΙΓΝΙΑ: Athenaeus 322A and Plin. H. N. 28.38,” Classical Quarterly 48.1 (1998): 262–68, https://doi.org/10.2307/639768; Betz, The Greek Magical Papyri, 119–20; James N. Davidson, “Don’t Try This at Home: Pliny’s Salpe, Salpe’s Paignia and Magic,” Classical Quarterly 45.2 (1995): 590–92, https://doi.org/10.2307/639553. ↵
- The setting of the Paignia of Democritus. For similar dinner party tricks see Athenaeus, 2.52d, 2.57b–d, 2.58f, 2.69f, 3.84c; Pliny, Nat. 35.50.175; Aulus Gellius, NA 1.38. ↵
- For Salpe, see Pliny, Nat. 28.7.38, 28.18.66, 28.23.82, 28.80.262, 32.47.135, 32.51.140. See also Athenaeus, 322a. For Anaxilaus see, for example, Epiphanius, Panarion 34.1; Pliny, Nat. 35.50.175. For similar tricks, see Lucian, Alex. 12, 14, 19–21; Achilles Tatius, 3.15–20. ↵
- Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World, 218. ↵
- Hippocrates, Morb. Sacr. 2.30 ↵
- Philostratus, Vit. Apoll. 7.39. See Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion, 66. It is also similar to the "secondary rationalisations" suggested by Evans-Pritchard to explain why, regardless of experience, magic was not thought to fail. See Glucklich, The End of Magic, 210. The idea that the validation of magic is fundamentally social — that is, it requires the validation of clients, an element of Philostratus' critique — also has analogies with the insights of Mauss. See Mauss, A General Theory of Magic, 150. ↵
- Pliny, Nat. 18.8.41–43. ↵
- Lindquist, Conjuring Hope. ↵
- For a study of how magic in antiquity was indeed deployed in response to such experiences, see Fritz Graf, “How to Cope with a Difficult Life : A View of Ancient Magic,” in Envisioning Magic: A Princeton Symposium, ed. Peter Schäfer and Hans Kippenberg (Leiden: Brill, 1997), 93–114. ↵
- Lindquist, Conjuring Hope, 2. ↵
- Lindquist, Conjuring Hope, 234. In making this distinction she is using Niklas Luhmann, Risk (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1993), 30. ↵
- Lindquist, Conjuring Hope, 234. ↵
- Jean-Claude Schmitt, Ghosts in the Middle Ages: The Living and the Dead in Medieval Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 7. ↵
- Exemplified by the failure of one of Lindquist's informants, a formerly impoverished businessman, to mention that he had consulted a magical practitioner when providing an account of the past; he now speaks in "didactic monologues on the worth of having done it all by himself". Lindquist, Conjuring Hope, 226. ↵
- For Kleinman's "explanatory model", see Arthur Kleinman, Leon Eisenberg, and Byron Good, “Culture, Illness, and Care,” Annals of Internal Medicine 88.2 (1978): 251–88. ↵
- See Tertullian, An. 57. Studies of formative Christianity and magic are numerous. See, for example, Arnold, Ephesians; Aune, “Magic in Early Christianity”; Garrett, “Light on a Dark Subject”; Garrett, The Demise of the Devil; John M. Hull, Hellenistic Magic and the Synoptic Tradition, SBT 2.28 (London: SCM Press, 1974); Howard Clark Kee, Medicine, Miracle and Magic in New Testament Times, SNTSMS 55 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986); Klauck, Magic and Paganism in Early Christianity; Todd Klutz, Magic in the Biblical World: From the Rod of Aaron to the Ring of Solomon, JSNTSup 245 (London: T&T Clark, 2003); Michael Labahn and Bert Jan Lietaert Peerbolte, eds., A Kind of Magic: Understanding Magic in the New Testament and Its Religious Environment, LNTS 306 (London: T&T Clark, 2007); Justin J. Meggitt, “Magic, Healing and Early Christianity: Consumption and Competition,” in Meanings of Magic: From the Bible to Buffalo Bill, ed. Amy Wygant (New York, NY: Berghahn Books, 2006), 89–114; Reimer, Miracle and Magic: A Study in the Acts of the Apostles and the Life of Apollonius of Tyana; Smith, Jesus the Magician; Smith, “How Magic Was Changed by the Triumph of Christianity,” in Studies in the Cult of Yahweh. Volume Two: New Testament, Early Christianity, Magic, ed. Shaye J. D. Cohen, Religions in the Graeco-Roman World 130 (Leiden: Brill, 1996), 208–16; Francis C. R. Thee, Julius Africanus and the Early Christian View of Magic, HUT 19 (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 1984); Rodney L. Thomas, Magical Motifs in the Book of Revelation, LNTS 416 (London: T&T Clark, 2010). The possibility that the nature and intensity of belief in magic can fluctuate as a result of ideological changes can be seen by the examination of comparative data. See, for example, Norman Cohn, Europe’s Inner Demons: The Demonization of Christians in Medieval Christendom, 2nd ed. (London: Pimlico, 1993); Valerie Flint, The Rise of Magic in Early Medieval Europe (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991); Gerrie ter Haar, ed., Imagining Evil: Witchcraft Beliefs and Accusations in Contemporary Africa (Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press, 2006); Jean S. La Fontaine, Speak of the Devil: Tales of Satanic Abuse in Contemporary England (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 190–92; Lindquist, Conjuring Hope; Keith Thomas, Religion and the Decline of Magic: Studies in Popular Beliefs in Sixteenth and Seventeenth Century England (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1971), 755–800. However, it is important to attend to the definitional assumptions about what constitutes "magic" in these works, which are varied and can be problematic. See, for example, Geertz's criticism of Thomas, Religion and the Decline of Magic, and Kieckhefer's criticism of Flint, The Rise of Magic in Early Medieval Europe, found in Geertz, “An Anthropology of Religion and Magic, I” and Richard Kieckhefer, “The Specific Rationality of Medieval Magic,” The American Historical Review 99.3 (1994): 813–36, https://doi.org/10.2307/2167771. ↵