6 Seditious Libel and Incitement to Illegal Action


Holmes’s motivations in his now-famous dissent are still unclear. On the one hand, the language in his dissent suggests he may have experienced a “road to Damascus” moment in the months following his Debs opinion and now favored stronger protections for speech. On the other hand, his dissent could also be explained by a belief that while Schenck and Debs had demonstrated their specific intent to incite illegal activity, the petitioners in Abrams had not. Regardless, Holmes and Brandeis would thereafter dissent from the Court’s use of the bad tendency approach.

Eventually, the supply of prosecutions from the Espionage Act came to an end as the war concluded. The tumult of ideological disagreement, the backlash against immigration, and elite fear of radicalism, however, continued on. The legal battle over free speech moved from the federal Espionage Act to the application of state laws, specifically so-called criminal syndicalism statutes. These state laws—aimed at communists or other groups which preached general strikes or (violent) revolution as a means of political change—made it a crime to advocate change through force or violence.

Of course, if the First Amendment did not apply to the states, then there was no role for the Supreme Court here. However, in surprisingly casual fashion, the Supreme Court held in Gitlow v. New York (1925), a case where Gitlow challenged New York’s criminal syndicalism law as violating the First Amendment, that:

… we may and do assume that freedom of speech and of the press—which are protected by the First Amendment from abridgement by Congress—are among the fundamental personal rights protected by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment from impairment by the states.

Of course, this act of incorporation was paired with the application of the bad tendency test, upholding New York’s power to punish speech. Nevertheless, the decision to incorporate the free speech (and press) clause would have far-reaching implications once future courts adopted more protective standards for speech.


Gitlow v. New York


268 U.S. 652 (1925)

Facts: Gitlow (a member of the Socialist Party) published and distributed the “Left-Wing Manifesto,” which argued for fundamental political change through general strikes and “class action.” He was convicted by New York for engaging in criminal anarchy, defined as advocating that government should be overturned by force or violence.

Question: Does New York’s criminal syndicalism law violate the First Amendment?

Vote: No, 7-2

For the Court: Justice Sanford

Dissenting opinion: Justice Holmes

JUSTICE SANFORD delivered the opinion of the court.

Benjamin Gitlow was indicted in the Supreme Court of New York, with three others, for the statutory crime of criminal anarchy…

The indictment was in two counts. The first charged that the defendant had advocated, advised and taught the duty, necessity and propriety of overthrowing and overturning organized government by force, violence and unlawful means, by certain writings therein set forth entitled “The Left Wing Manifesto”; the second, that he had printed, published and knowingly circulated and distributed a certain paper called “The Revolutionary Age,” containing the writings set forth in the first count advocating, advising and teaching the doctrine that organized government should be overthrown by force, violence and unlawful means…

There was no evidence of any effect resulting from the publication and circulation of the Manifesto…

The sole contention here is, essentially, that as there was no evidence of any concrete result flowing from the publication of the Manifesto or of circumstances showing the likelihood of such result, the statute as construed and applied by the trial court penalizes the mere utterance, as such, of “doctrine” having no quality of incitement, without regard either to the circumstances of its utterance or to the likelihood of unlawful sequences, and that, as the exercise of the right of free expression with relation to government is only punishable “in circumstances involving likelihood of substantive evil,” the statute contravenes the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The argument in support of this contention rests primarily upon the following propositions: 1st, that the “liberty” protected by the Fourteenth Amendment includes the liberty of speech and of the press, and 2nd, that while liberty of expression “is not absolute,” it may be restrained “only in circumstances where its exercise bears a causal relation with some substantive evil, consummated, attempted or likely,” and as the statute “takes no account of circumstances,” it unduly restrains this liberty and is therefore unconstitutional…

The statute does not penalize the utterance or publication of abstract “doctrine” or academic discussion having no quality of incitement to any concrete action. It is not aimed against mere historical or philosophical essays. It does not restrain the advocacy of changes in the form of government by constitutional and lawful means. What it prohibits is language advocating, advising or teaching the overthrow of organized government by unlawful means. These words imply urging to action…

The Manifesto, plainly, is neither the statement of abstract doctrine nor, as suggested by counsel, mere prediction that industrial disturbances and revolutionary mass strikes will result spontaneously in an inevitable process of evolution in the economic system. It advocates and urges in fervent language mass action which shall progressively foment industrial disturbances and, through political mass strikes and revolutionary mass action, overthrow and destroy organized parliamentary government. It concludes with a call to action…

For present purposes, we may and do assume that freedom of speech and of the press which are protected by the First Amendment from abridgment by Congress are among the fundamental personal rights and “liberties” protected by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment from impairment by the States…

It is a fundamental principle, long established, that the freedom of speech and of the press which is secured by the Constitution does not confer an absolute right to speak or publish, without responsibility, whatever one may choose, or an unrestricted and unbridled license that gives immunity for every possible use of language and prevents the punishment of those who abuse this freedom… Reasonably limited, it was said by [Justice] Story in the passage cited, this freedom is an inestimable privilege in a free government; without such limitation, it might become the scourge of the republic.

That a State in the exercise of its police power may punish those who abuse this freedom by utterances inimical to the public welfare, tending to corrupt public morals, incite to crime, or disturb the public peace, is not open to question…

And, for yet more imperative reasons, a State may punish utterances endangering the foundations of organized government and threatening its overthrow by unlawful means. These imperil its own existence as a constitutional State. Freedom of speech and press … does not protect disturbances to the public peace or the attempt to subvert the government. It does not protect publications or teachings which tend to subvert or imperil the government or to impede or hinder it in the performance of its governmental duties. It does not protect publications prompting the overthrow of government by force; the punishment of those who publish articles which tend to destroy organized society being essential to the security of freedom and the stability of the State. And a State may penalize utterances which openly advocate the overthrow of the representative and constitutional form of government of the United States and the several States, by violence or other unlawful means. In short, this freedom does not deprive a State of the primary and essential right of self-preservation, which, so long as human governments endure, they cannot be denied…

That utterances inciting to the overthrow of organized government by unlawful means present a sufficient danger of substantive evil to bring their punishment within the range of legislative discretion is clear. Such utterances, by their very nature, involve danger to the public peace and to the security of the State. They threaten breaches of the peace, and ultimate revolution. And the immediate danger is none the less real and substantial because the effect of a given utterance cannot be accurately foreseen. The State cannot reasonably be required to measure the danger from every such utterance in the nice balance of a jeweler’s scale. A single revolutionary spark may kindle a fire that, smouldering for a time, may burst into a sweeping and destructive conflagration. It cannot be said that the State is acting arbitrarily or unreasonably when, in the exercise of its judgment as to the measures necessary to protect the public peace and safety, it seeks to extinguish the spark without waiting until it has enkindled the flame or blazed into the conflagration. It cannot reasonably be required to defer the adoption of measures for its own peace and safety until the revolutionary utterances lead to actual disturbances of the public peace or imminent and immediate danger of its own destruction; but it may, in the exercise of its judgment, suppress the threatened danger in its incipiency.

We cannot hold that the present statute is an arbitrary or unreasonable exercise of the police power of the State unwarrantably infringing the freedom of speech or press, and we must and do sustain its constitutionality…

And the general statement in the Schenck Case that the

question in every case is whether the words are used in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils

— upon which great reliance is placed in the defendant’s argument — was manifestly intended, as shown by the context, to apply only in cases of this class, and has no application to those like the present, where the legislative body itself has previously determined the danger of substantive evil arising from utterances of a specified character…

JUSTICE HOLMES, dissenting.

JUSTICE BRANDEIS and I are of opinion that this judgment should be reversed. The general principle of free speech, it seems to me, must be taken to be included in the Fourteenth Amendment, in view of the scope that has been given to the word “liberty” as there used, although perhaps it may be accepted with a somewhat larger latitude of interpretation than is allowed to Congress by the sweeping language that governs or ought to govern the laws of the United States. If I am right, then I think that the criterion sanctioned by the full Court in Schenck v. United States applies:

The question in every case is whether the words used are used in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils that [the State] has a right to prevent.

It is true that, in my opinion, this criterion was departed from in Abrams v. United States, but the convictions that I expressed in that case are too deep for it to be possible for me as yet to believe that it … [has] settled the law. If what I think the correct test is applied, it is manifest that there was no present danger of an attempt to overthrow the government by force on the part of the admittedly small minority who shared the defendant’s views. It is said that this manifesto was more than a theory, that it was an incitement. Every idea is an incitement. It offers itself for belief, and, if believed, it is acted on unless some other belief outweighs it or some failure of energy stifles the movement at its birth. The only difference between the expression of an opinion and an incitement in the narrower sense is the speaker’s enthusiasm for the result. Eloquence may set fire to reason. But whatever may be thought of the redundant discourse before us, it had no chance of starting a present conflagration. If, in the long run, the beliefs expressed in proletarian dictatorship are destined to be accepted by the dominant forces of the community, the only meaning of free speech is that they should be given their chance and have their way.

If the publication of this document had been laid as an attempt to induce an uprising against government at once, and not at some indefinite time in the future, it would have presented a different question. The object would have been one with which the law might deal, subject to the doubt whether there was any danger that the publication could produce any result, or in other words, whether it was not futile and too remote from possible consequences. But the indictment alleges the publication, and nothing more.

Questions

1. Justice Sandford’s opinion contains the most memorable analogy in defense of the bad tendency test, that a “single revolutionary spark may kindle a fire that, smouldering for a time, may burst into a sweeping and destructive conflagration.” Is this an accurate depiction of how speech or ideas can lead people to action? What problems does it create as a standard for protecting speech?

2. Sanford’s opinion also contains a “self-defense” argument, that democracies should be permitted to ban speech by those who would end democracy or create political change through force or violence (this distinction, he argues, makes these cases different from those produced by Espionage Act convictions, and justifies not using the clear and present danger test). Is “self-preservation” a reasonable defense of censorship of speech? Do you think such laws can have the self-preserving effect that Sanford ascribes to them? What rights do we owe to those who might not protect our rights in turn, if they obtained power?

3. Justice Holmes, in reiterating his support for the clear and present danger test, says a call to immediate action might justify government punishment in a way that Gitlow’s more indefinite call for action does not. Why should it matter whether the danger is immediate or far off? How might Holmes’s “marketplace of ideas” concept be influencing his thinking here?

4. The final sentence of Holmes’s dissent suggests a sort of fatalism: if the public wants a “proletarian dictatorship” [a communist revolution], then free speech requires allowing the majority to express those beliefs. In other words, we can’t legislate away bad ideas. What do you think of this viewpoint? Does the government have a role in combatting the rise of dangerous, anti-democratic, or morally reprehensible ideas? Or must such fights be left to the marketplace of ideas, our culture, and so on?

In line with the bad tendency test and the general opinion of the era, federal courts rejected challenges to criminal syndicalism laws just as they rejected Espionage Act challenges in the years before. There would be no substantive revisiting of the incitement standard until the 1950s.

One final opinion is worthy of note. In Whitney v. California (1927), the Court upheld a criminal syndicalism conviction of Charlotte Whitney, a member and organizer of the California chapter of the Communist Labor Party. Whitney argued that as a member of the group, she had been a moderating force who rejected calls for general strikes or violence and advocated for peaceful change through the political process. Despite these claims (for which she had supporting evidence), she was nevertheless convicted.

The Court upheld the conviction on the same 7-2 split seen in Abrams and Gitlow. Justice Sanford’s majority opinion echoes his opinion in Gitlow and need not be reproduced here. Justice Brandeis’s striking concurrence (he agreed with the conviction because Whitney had not properly raised the First Amendment issues at trial but disagreed with the Court’s reasoning), however, contains a powerful defense of his position and is worth excerpting at length:

…This Court has not yet fixed the standard by which to determine when a danger shall be deemed clear; how remote the danger may be and yet be deemed present, and what degree of evil shall be deemed sufficiently substantial to justify resort to abridgement of free speech and assembly as the means of protection. To reach sound conclusions on these matters, we must bear in mind why a State is, ordinarily, denied the power to prohibit dissemination of social, economic and political doctrine which a vast majority of its citizens believes to be false and fraught with evil consequence.

Those who won our independence believed that the final end of the State was to make men free to develop their faculties, and that, in its government, the deliberative forces should prevail over the arbitrary. They valued liberty both as an end, and as a means. They believed liberty to be the secret of happiness, and courage to be the secret of liberty. They believed that freedom to think as you will and to speak as you think are means indispensable to the discovery and spread of political truth; that, without free speech and assembly, discussion would be futile; that, with them, discussion affords ordinarily adequate protection against the dissemination of noxious doctrine; that the greatest menace to freedom is an inert people; that public discussion is a political duty, and that this should be a fundamental principle of the American government. They recognized the risks to which all human institutions are subject. But they knew that order cannot be secured merely through fear of punishment for its infraction; that it is hazardous to discourage thought, hope and imagination; that fear breeds repression; that repression breeds hate; that hate menaces stable government; that the path of safety lies in the opportunity to discuss freely supposed grievances and proposed remedies, and that the fitting remedy for evil counsels is good ones. Believing in the power of reason as applied through public discussion, they eschewed silence coerced by law — the argument of force in its worst form. Recognizing the occasional tyrannies of governing majorities, they amended the Constitution so that free speech and assembly should be guaranteed.

Fear of serious injury cannot alone justify suppression of free speech and assembly. Men feared witches and burnt women. It is the function of speech to free men from the bondage of irrational fears. To justify suppression of free speech, there must be reasonable ground to fear that serious evil will result if free speech is practiced. There must be reasonable ground to believe that the danger apprehended is imminent. There must be reasonable ground to believe that the evil to be prevented is a serious one. Every denunciation of existing law tends in some measure to increase the probability that there will be violation of it. Condonation of a breach enhances the probability. Expressions of approval add to the probability. Propagation of the criminal state of mind by teaching syndicalism increases it. Advocacy of law-breaking heightens it still further. But even advocacy of violation, however reprehensible morally, is not a justification for denying free speech where the advocacy falls short of incitement and there is nothing to indicate that the advocacy would be immediately acted on. The wide difference between advocacy and incitement, between preparation and attempt, between assembling and conspiracy, must be borne in mind. In order to support a finding of clear and present danger, it must be shown either that immediate serious violence was to be expected or was advocated, or that the past conduct furnished reason to believe that such advocacy was then contemplated.

Those who won our independence by revolution were not cowards. They did not fear political change. They did not exalt order at the cost of liberty. To courageous, self-reliant men, with confidence in the power of free and fearless reasoning applied through the processes of popular government, no danger flowing from speech can be deemed clear and present unless the incidence of the evil apprehended is so imminent that it may befall before there is opportunity for full discussion. If there be time to expose through discussion the falsehood and fallacies, to avert the evil by the processes of education, the remedy to be applied is more speech, not enforced silence. Only an emergency can justify repression. Such must be the rule if authority is to be reconciled with freedom. Such, in my opinion, is the command of the Constitution. It is therefore always open to Americans to challenge a law abridging free speech and assembly by showing that there was no emergency justifying it.

Moreover, even imminent danger cannot justify resort to prohibition of these functions essential to effective democracy unless the evil apprehended is relatively serious. Prohibition of free speech and assembly is a measure so stringent that it would be inappropriate as the means for averting a relatively trivial harm to society. A police measure may be unconstitutional merely because the remedy, although effective as means of protection, is unduly harsh or oppressive. Thus, a State might, in the exercise of its police power, make any trespass upon the land of another a crime, regardless of the results or of the intent or purpose of the trespasser. It might, also, punish an attempt, a conspiracy, or an incitement to commit the trespass. But it is hardly conceivable that this Court would hold constitutional a statute which punished as a felony the mere voluntary assembly with a society formed to teach that pedestrians had the moral right to cross unenclosed, unposted, wastelands and to advocate their doing so, even if there was imminent danger that advocacy would lead to a trespass. The fact that speech is likely to result in some violence or in destruction of property is not enough to justify its suppression. There must be the probability of serious injury to the State. Among free men, the deterrents ordinarily to be applied to prevent crime are education and punishment for violations of the law, not abridgment of the rights of free speech and assembly…

Questions

1. After reading this excerpt, look back at how Brandeis describes the motivations or beliefs of the framers of the constitution. Does his description track with what we have read so far? What does his opinion suggest to you about how we use the Founding generation in making arguments about politics?

2. Brandeis had a different set of predictions about the regulation of speech than those who argued for wide-ranging state power to punish speech. For example, he argues that suppression of speech leads to greater instability than combatting “bad” views through public discussion; that the answer to bad speech is more speech, not censorship or punishment; that it’s a greater danger to grant the state the power to suppress dangerous speech than to let such speech take place.

What do you think of these arguments? Do they hold up in an era of social media?

definition

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License

Civil Liberties: Cases and Materials Copyright © 2021 by Rob Robinson is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book