6

 

Learning Objectives

By the end of this chapter, you should be able to,

  • identify intermediate levels (“bar levels”) using constituency tests
  • understand the motivation for the X-bar schema
  • draw a tree using the X-bar schema,
  • identify the distinct positions within the X-bar schema,
  • diagnose the difference between adjuncts and complements

By the end of this chapter, we will have technically changed theories. We’re going from Phrase Structure Grammars to X-bar Syntax. But the trick is to recognize that, even though we’re going to be using the term “X-bar syntax,” we aren’t actually changing theories at all. The same principles, formalizations, and theoretical tools will be used in X-bar syntax that we’ve already been using. Our trees are just going to look more complicated. The reason that our trees will look more complicated is that we’re going to discover in this chapter that there are lot of “hidden” layers. Just like when we discussed functional categories we learned to infer the presence of structure, even when we can’t directly see it, we’ll use the same tools to infer the presence of “bar-levels.”

From this, we’ll make a theoretical leap. As a hypothesis about syntax, we’ll adopt a uniform structural representation for all phrases. This is “X-bar syntax.” It’s the hypothesis that all phrases share a structure, i.e., every phrase looks identical. The hypothesis makes a number of testable predictions, which we’ll explore in terms of the complement/adjunct distinction.

Deconstructing VP

Let’s start by looking again at English VPs. Assume the (very simplistic) rule for VPs below.

Simplified VP rule for English (to be revised)

  • VP → V (DP) (PP)+

This rule allows us to minimally distinguish between transitive and intransitive verbs, each of which could have a modifying prepositional phrase. For instance, using this VP rule, here’s the structure for The doctor will sing a song in the park.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

This tree correctly represents that in the park is a constituent. It also correctly represents that sing a song in the park is a constituent. However, it still is getting the constituency wrong. Look at the substitution test below. What does it show is a constituent?

\setcounter{ExNo}{1}  \ex. \a. The doctor will sing a song in the park. \b. and Mary will do so in the office.

What’s the problem here? The test demonstrates that sing a song is a constituent, because I am able to replace that string with do so. The tree in (1) gets this wrong. The string sing a song isn’t a constituent according to this tree because there is no node that contains the words sing a song and nothing else.

Is our constituency test just giving us a false positive? Let’s confirm. Below I’m applying the other constituency tests.

\setcounter{ExNo}{2}  \ex. Fragments\\ What will the doctor do in the park? {\underline{Sing a song}}  \ex. \a. \textit{It}-Clefting\\ {}*It was {\underline{sing a song}} that the doctor will do in the park. \b. Pseudo-clefting\\ {\underline{Sing a song}} is what the doctor will do in the park. \c. \textit{All}-clefting\\ {\underline{Sing a song}} is all the doctor will do in the park. \d. Topicalization\\ {}*{\underline{Sing a song}}, the doctor will do in the park.  \ex. Coordination\\ The doctor will [ sing a song ] and [ dance ] in the park

So our constituency tests are telling us that sing a song is a constituent—and that it’s a VP. Recall that substitution and coordination allow us to diagnose the category of the constituent.  But here’s the thing: the string sing a song in the park is also a VP. How do I know? It passes all the same constituency tests, and we can detect its category through substitution and coordination.

\setcounter{ExNo}{5}  \ex. Substitution\\ The doctor will {\underline{sing a song in the park}}, and the nurse will {\underline{do so}}, too  \ex. Fragments\\ What will the doctor do? {\underline{Sing a song in the park}}  \ex. \a. \textit{It}-Clefting\\ {}*It was {\underline{sing a song in the park}} that the doctor will do. \b. Pseudo-clefting\\ {\underline{Sing a song in the park}} is what the doctor will do. \c. \textit{All}-clefting\\ {\underline{Sing a song in the park}} is all the doctor will do. \d. Topicalization\\ {}*{\underline{Sing a song in the park}}, the doctor will do.  \ex. Coordination\\ The doctor will [ sing a song in the park ] and [ dance at home ]

So based on this evidence, it looks like our tree should actually have the following representation.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

This version of the tree correctly captures our empirical result: we have two distinct VP constituents. (It also correctly predicts that a song in the park is not a constituent, which you can confirm on your own.) The “trick” is that we’ve added a VP in-between the head and the highest VP. This projection is empirically motivated, though. It’s there because our tests tell us it’s there. (Note that technically, the highest VP violates the Headedness Principle.)

We call this intermediate projection the “bar” level, and write it either with a line over the top (V) or an apostrophe after (V’). It’s pronounced “V bar” (not “V prime”). This is just a notation for saying “I’m not the highest phrase in this phrase.”

To review: we’ve used our constituency tests to determine that there is a “hidden” level in verb phrases.

Let’s look at more data.

\setcounter{ExNo}{10}  \ex. \a. John will sing a song on a bike in the park and Mary will do so at the office. \b. John will sing a song on a bike and dance a jig at the park at different times.

These data are just like the data above, except that I’ve added in more prepositional phrases. So now sing a song on a bike can’t be the highest VP in the structure. The highest VP is the entire constituent sing a song on a bike in the park. This is the topmost VP. Now in fact, we need two intermediate projections, because the constituents sing a song and sing a song on a bike and sing a song on a bike in the park are all VPs.

\setcounter{ExNo}{11}  \ex. [ John will [$_{VP}$ [$_{V'}$ [$_{V'}$ sing a song ] on a bike ] in the park ] ]

These data actually suggest that I can simplify my representation quite a bit, because they suggest that I can make do without the “+” symbol. All I need are three rules like the following. Note that three rules is actually simpler than one rule with a plus sign because now we can get by with less formalism. By analogy, 2 + 2 + 2 is simpler than 2 x 3 because it provides the same information with a less complex operator.

Simplified VP rule for English (revised)

  • VP → V’
  • V’ → V’ PP
  • V’ → V (DP)

I’ve done a very tricky (but ultimately useful) thing here. I’ve explicitly added recursion into my English phrase structure grammar. There’s a rule that says V’ (i.e., an intermediate projection between the head and the topmost VP) can consist of itself and a prepositional phrase. Why does this work? Consider the tree for John will sing a song on a bike in the park which uses the new rule above.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

When I build a VP now, I have an option: I can either add in an infinite number of prepositional phrases by adding in a new V’ level, or I can just go directly to the head V. I’ve essentially created a way to make an infinitely recursive loop—with an escape hatch. Most importantly, all of these intermediate projections correlate with distinct, identifiable constituents.  That is, our structure correctly represents how English packages its information.

Deconstructing TP

We can do the exact same thing with TP. Let’s assume our rule for TP developed in the last chapter.

TP rule for English (to be revised)

  • TP → DP T VP

Now consider the following data, which suggests that there is a bar-level—an intermediate projection—in TP.

\setcounter{ExNo}{13}  \ex. \a. John will eat sushi and will drink sake. \b. Mary has forgiven Jed and might forgive Brad. \c. Conrad can sing and could dance.

What is this data showing? It shows that I can coordinate will eat sushi with something else. That is, there appears to be a constituent that include T and VP, but does not include the subject. This is not possible, according to our rule above. To fix this issue, we can re-write our rule, parallel to what we did with VP.

TP rule for English (revised)

  • TP → DP T’
  • T’ → T VP

Adding in this extra level correctly captures what our constituency test is telling us.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

This tree now correctly captures the fact that T forms a constituent with VP, to the exclusion of the subject. That constituent is the bar level, T’.

What if I add in more words. Here I’m adding a modifier of TP.

\setcounter{ExNo}{14} \ex. \a. John definitely will eat sushi and probably will drink sake. \b. John definitely will eat sushi and drink sake.

This data now suggests that the modifier gets grouped together with T and the VP in the first example (because both constituents have a similar modifier), but in the second example shows us that T and the VP can form a constituent that is separate from this modifier (because definitely is describing both the eating and drinking events). How are we going to make this work? If Adverbs[1] like definitely, probably, etc may sometimes be distinct from the VP, and sometimes not, we need to adjust our rules about where adverbs go in TP.

Just like with VP, we can fix this issue concisely by adding a recursive T’ level!

TP rule for English (revised)

  • TP → DP T’
  • T’ → AdvP T’
  • T’ → T VP

This set of rules allows us to add as many modifiers of TP as we want, and we will always find that each additional modifier “creates” a subconstituent within TP.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Deconstructing NP

We’ll do the exact same thing with NP. Keep in mind that we’ve adopted the DP-hypothesis, so all NPs are inside of DPs.

Simplified NP rule for English (to be revised)

  • NP → (AP)+ N

With this rule in mind, consider the patterns of one substitution shown below.

\setcounter{ExNo}{15}  \ex. \a. Tricia read the short book, not the long one. \b. Tricia read the short blue book, not the long one.

We observed in the last chapter that one substituted for NP, but these data suggest that that isn’t quite accurate. One must be substituting for something between NP and N. Consider (16b). One is replacing the constituent blue book. This includes an adjective, so it’s not just the head N, but it excludes the higher adjective short/long, so this cannot be the entire NP.

We therefore find evidence in NP for an intermediate projection, and we re-write our rules accordingly. Now we can add in an infinite number of prenominal adjectives by adding in more intermediate projections.

Simplified NP rule for English (revised)

  • NP → N’
  • N’ → AdjP N’
  • N’ → N

These rules correspond to the following tree.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Generalizing across categories

When we look across all of our rules, we can make a few generalizations:

  • There’s always a rule of the form XP → X’, where the phrase level goes to the intermediate level. (Sometimes this rule has an element in front of X’.)
  • There’s always a rule of the form X’ → X, where the bar-level consists of the head. (Sometimes the head is followed by something on the right.)
  • There’s always a recursive rule of the form X’ →YP X’ or X’ → X’ YP, where YP is a modifier of some sort.

If this pattern exists for every single category, it suggests that we can generalize our schema for phrase structure. We hypothesize that every phrase has the following rules. The “X, Y, Z, W” below are variables meaning “any category.”

Generalized phrase structures rules (final version)

  • XP → (YP) X’
  • X’ → X’ ZP
  • X’ → ZP X’
  • X’ → X (WP)

If this is right, it means that all phrases are constructed based on these rules. In the rules above X, Y, and W are variables over categories.

What about the Headedness Principle? Have we entirely abandoned it? No! The Headedness Principle, which says that every phrase has a head and every head is in its phrase is exactly the same. But we’ve redefined what “phrase” meansNow a phrase minimally involves at least one X’-level.  A phrase consists of all of the rules above: it is the X-bar schema. The term “phrase” is now a structural notion.

The X-bar schema is a hypothesis. By looking at a lot of data, we identify that there are intermediate projections in every phrase that we look at. The subsequent phrase structure rules all end up looking very similar—suspiciously similar in fact. The X-bar schema is a way to make sense of this information. It proposes that the similarities reflect a “deep” uniformity across syntax. Our trees end up looking more complex, because now everything needs at least one intermediate projection. But the complexity of the representations comes with an overall simplification of the theory: it isn’t necessary to learn a bunch of arbitrary rules for syntax. You only need the four above, because they apply to every phrasal category.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

 

Trees in the X’ schema (length: 1m 28s)

Note we also still need special rules for coordination, which look basically the same as before.

Rules for coordination (final version)

  • XP → XP conj XP
  • X’ → X’ conj X’
  • X → X conj X

These rules allow you to coordinate heads (X), bar-levels (X’) and phrases (XP), but you can’t mix-and-match. You cannot coordinate a bar level with a head, for instance.

Positions in X’-syntax

We define four positions within the X’-schema: specifier, head, complement and adjunct. The positions are indicated in the trees below.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

  • A head is the only non-phrasal terminal node in a phrase.
  • A specifier is defined as, “The phrase that is daughter of XP and sister to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is a specifier.
  • A complement is defined as, “The phrase that is sister to X and daughter to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is a complement.[2]
  • An adjunct is defined as, “The phrase that is daughter to X and sister to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is an adjunct.

Positions in X’-Syntax (length: 1m 53s) credit: Kyra Schrock

Note that the definitions above do not make reference to linear order. It doesn’t matter whether an adjunct is to the left or the right. All that matters is that its sister and mother are bar-levels. Likewise, complements can be on the left or the right of a head, as long as it is sister to the head. And a specifier can be on the left right as well, as long its mother is a phrase. Every language makes particular choices however about where specifiers and complements appear. We’ll return to this momentarily. For now, we note that in English, specifiers are always on the left, and complements are always on the right.

It is conventional to use the “genealogical” terms mother, sister, and daughter when referring to the relationships between elements in a tree. The terms are meant to be transparent: A “mother” is something that has “daughters.” If two things have the same mother, then they’re “sisters.”

In the tree below, DP is the mother of D’. D’ is the mother of D and NP. D and NP are sisters, and are both daughters of D’.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

The analogy basically stops there. There is no such thing as an “aunt” in syntax, or a “niece.”

We’ve seen a lot of complements. TP is a complement to CP. NP is a complement to D. DP can be a complement to V when it’s an object of the verb. The only specifier we’ve seen is the subject. It’s the specifier of TP. There is another place where a specifier is necessary: DP.

Possessive structure.

The other place where we observe specifiers is in possessive DPs.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

We treat the possessive marker -s as a realization of D. This is because possessives are in complementary distribution with determiners: *the mailman’s the bag. And because the entire DP acts as a constituent referring to a bag, not a mailman, the head of the highest DP must be the possessive D.

Possessive DPs (length: 1m 51s)

Complements vs. Adjuncts

The X-bar schema illustrated above makes a prediction that some phrases that are next to a head are complements while some are adjuncts. They may look identical on the surface, but they derive from different structures.

For instance, consider the phrase the state of Kansas. In the X-bar schema, this constituent (and it definitely is a constituent) could hypothetically correspond to either tree below. The prepositional phrase of Kansas could either be a complement to state (as in the tree on the left) or an adjunct to state (as in the tree on the right).

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

The two trees actually make distinct empirical predictions. We have three tests to distinguish between complements and adjuncts.

First, I just want to briefly mention that it is easy to confuse adjuncts and specifiers. When drawing your trees, remember that for every adjunct, you should have “plus one” bar-level, because adjuncts need both a bar-level which is a sister, and bar-level which is a mother. So you have to add a layer whenever you add an adjunct.

Adjuncts in X’-syntax (length: 2m 15s)

Substitution

The constituency test of substitution has a different use. As we observed above, one substitution and do so substitution both target the bar-level. Since complements are under all bar-levels in a phrase, if you try to do substitution, a complement cannot be “left behind.” An adjunct can, though, because there’s always a bar-level that doesn’t include the adjunct.

Visually, consider the two trees again. If the PP is a complement to N, then when you substitute with one everything under N’ has to go too. In contrast, if the PP is an adjunct, it’s possible to substitute with one and leave behind the PP.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

So to use the substitution test to determine if something is a complement or adjunct, you simply replace the head of the phrase, and see if you can leave behind the constituent in question.

Compare the sentences below.

\setcounter{ExNo}{18}  \ex. \a. the state of Kansas, and\\ {}*the one of Maine \b. the state near Kansas, and\\ {} the one near Maine.

As illustrated above, one-substitution crucially yields an ungrammatical result in (19a), but not in (19b). Why is this? Again, note here that one-substitution targets bar-levels; you can only replace the material that exists under a bar-level. As such, the reason for the grammaticality distinction in the examples above is that the NPs, the state of Kansas and the state near Kansas, crucially differ in the number of bar-levels they contain. That is, unlike in the NP, [ NP  state of Kansas ], where one-substitution can replace both N and PP (20a), but not  N alone (20b), with the NP, [ NP state near Kansas ], one-substitution can  either replace the larger constituent containing N and PP (21a), or N alone (21b), meaning that the NP in (19) must crucially contain two bar-levels, and the NP in (20), only one. 

 

\setcounter{ExNo}{19}  \ex.  I visited the state of Kansas. \\ \a. I visited the \textit{one}.  \hfill ( targets: [  \textsubscript{N'} [\textsubscript{N} state ][ \textsubscript{PP} of Kansas ]] ) \\\b. *I visited the \textit{one} of Kansas. \hfill ( targets: [ \textsubscript{N'}  [ \textsubscript{N} state ]] )\\  \vspace{3mm}  \ex.  I visited the state near Kansas\\ \a. I visited the \textit{one}.  \hfill ( targets: [  \textsubscript{N'} [\textsubscript{N} state ][ \textsubscript{PP} near Kansas ]] )\\\b. I visited the \textit{one} near Kansas.   \hfill ( targets: [ \textsubscript{N'}  [ \textsubscript{N} state ]] )\\

Since we have defined a complement as being the sister of the head that selects it, and the daughter of the bar-level that contains that same head (i.e. a head and its complement share a bar-level parent), while conversely defining an adjunct as being both the sister to a bar-level and  the daughter to a  bar-level,  the fact that one-substitution can target two different constituents in (21) means that the NP, the state near Kansas, necessarily contains two bar-levels, and, therefore, must contain an adjunct. That is, the PP, near Kansas, must be an adjunct because there are two different targets (i.e. bar-levels) for one-substitution in (20); one can replace the lower bar-level to the exclusion of PP, i.e.  [ N’ [ N state ]],  or it can replace the higher bar-level that includes both the lower N’ and PP, i.e. [ N’ [N’  [ N state][ PP near Kansas ]]. 

 

Step-by-step walkthrough of the substitution test

  • Identify the head in question and the phrase which you want to test
  • Identify the appropriate substitution word for the head. 
  • Replace the head with the substitution word, but don’t replace the phrase you’re testing. (Note that technically, you’re substituting at the lowest bar-level, which contains the head. The lowest bar-level could, in principle also have a complement.)
  • Check the grammaticality.

Substitution test for complements vs. adjuncts (length: 1m 6s)

Substitution test for complements vs. adjuncts (length: 1m 9s) Credit Damian White Lightning

Reordering

Complements must appear as sisters to the head,  and so they have a fixed position with respect to other phrases. But adjuncts can, theoretically, be reordered. This is because all that’s necessary is that they have a mother that’s a bar-level and a sister that’s a bar-level.

For instance, consider the following trees which each have two prepositional phrases. The tree on the left treats PP1 as an complement and PP2 as an adjunct.  If we switched their positions, then we switch their roles.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

 

In contrast, in the tree on the right, both the PPs are adjuncts. It shouldn’t matter whether we switch their positions, because they both will still be adjuncts.

What this means is that if a constituent is a complement, it cannot be reordered with another constituent. If a constituent is an adjunct, it can be.

The difference can be shown empirically in the following examples. You can’t reorder of Kansas and near Maine, suggesting that of Kansas is a complement to state. In contrast, you can reorder by the ocean and near Maine, so we conclude that by the ocean is an adjunct to state.

\setcounter{ExNo}{20}  \ex. \a. the state of Kansas near Maine \b. *The state near Maine of Kansas  \ex. \a. the state by the ocean near Maine \b. the state near Maine by the ocean

Step-by-step walkthrough of the reordering test

  • Identify the head and the phrase which you want to test.
  • Choose an appropriate phrase that can appear with the head and phrase above.
  • Reorder or the two phrases with respect to the head, and check the grammaticality.

Reordering test (length: 1m 2s)

Reordering test (length: 1m 6s) Credit: Damian White Lightning

Sometimes we can’t reorder phrases for semantic reasons, independent (presumably) of syntax. There happens to be a fixed order for modification that is fairly robust cross-linguistically. For instance, temporal modifiers (things that deal with “time”) tend to be merged higher (or “outside”) of manner modifiers (things that describe “how” the event was accomplished). Likewise, there is a fairly fixed ordering of adjectives in English (and many languages).

\setcounter{ExNo}{21}  \ex. \a. Sammie cut Vaughn's hair {\underline{with scissors}} {\underline{often}} \b. ??Sammie cut Vaughn's hair {\underline{often}} {\underline{with scissors}}  \ex. \a. the big brown ball \b. ??the brown big ball

Linear ordering

As a corollary to the last test, if you can’t reorder the phrases, the phrase nearest the head must be a complement. In fact, we predict that complements are always strictly adjacent to the head. Therefore, it should be impossible to insert anything between a head and complement. (Note that this test is irrelevant (N/A) if you find that you can reorder the phrase in question.)

Again, the difference is shown empirically below.

\setcounter{ExNo}{22}  \ex. \a. *the state that I visited of Kansas \b. the state that I visited near Maine

Step-by-step walkthrough of linear ordering test

  • Identify the head and the phrase you want to know about.
  • Identify some other constituent that can also directly follow the head.
  • Put the phrase you want to know about after the new phrase, both after the head, and check the grammaticality.

Linear ordering test (length: 1m 10s)

The reason that this test works is that the relationship between the head and complement is fixed: they must be sisters. But the relationship between a head and an adjunct is not fixed; there can be any number of adjuncts be between the head and the adjunct.

Based on the three tests above, we find that of Kansas is a complement to state. So the following is the correct representation:

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Parameters

The order of the specifiers and complements is fixed for any one language. What does that mean? For instance, in English, the complement always comes after the head. That is, English is head-initial. With specifiers, the specifier always comes before the head. English is specifier-initial.

However, logically for each position, there are four ways things could be.

  • Specifier-initial :  The specifier is to the left of its head (meaning to the left of the bar-level).
  • Specifier-final : The specifier is to the right of its head (meaning to the right of the bar-level).
  • Head-initial : The head is the left of its complement.
  • Head-final : The head is to the right of its complement.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

It turns out that languages make different choices as to how they order their heads and specifiers (and adjuncts). This is called parametric variation.  English is specifier-initial and head-initial. Thus, in “neutral” contexts, it will have the order of Subject-Verb-Object, or SVO.

Kashaya (a Pomoan language spoken in Northern California) has set its parameters to specifier-initial and head-final. So it’s basic word order is “Subject-Object-Verb,” or SOV.

\setcounter{ExNo}{23}  Kashaya: \exg. Conrad Anita-to cadu\\ Conrad Anita-\textsc{acc} saw\\ \trans `Conrad saw Anita.'

Malagasy (an Austronesian language spoken on Madagascar) has set its parameters to specifier-final and head-initial. It’s basic word order is “Verb-Object-Subject,” or VOS.

\setcounter{ExNo}{24} Malagasy: \exg. nahita ny mpianatra ny vehivavay\\ saw the student the woman\\ \trans `The woman saw the student.''

Lastly, Hixkaryana (a Carib language spoken in Brazil) has set its parameters to specifier-final and head-final. So it’s basic word order is “Object-Verb-Subject,” or OVS.

\setcounter{ExNo}{25}  Hixkaryana: \exg. kana yan{\"i}mno b{\"i}yekomo\\ fish caught boy\\ \trans `The boy caught a fish.'

If you’re counting, you’ll notice that I’ve said nothing about whether the two other logically possible words orders of Subject, Verb, and Object exists: VSO and OSV. These cannot be straightforwardly derived by simply stipulating specifier and head directions. Something more (i.e., movement) must be added to the theory.

Nonetheless, K’iche’ (a Mayan language spoken in Guatemala) has a basic word order of “Verb-Subject-Object,” or VSO.

\setcounter{ExNo}{26}  \exg. xril la ali Marij la a Xwaan\\ saw \textsc{det} \textsc{fem} Mary \textsc{det} \textsc{masc} John\\ \trans `Mary saw John.'

OSV is incredibly rare. This points to a very interesting distributional fact: while all possible orders exist, they don’t all exist with the same frequency. SOV is the predominant word-order cross-linguistically, accounting for about 40% the world’s languages. Next is SVO, accounting for about another 35%. The other categories account for the remaining 25%.

Interestingly, languages tend to be largely consistent in their head and specifier settings. That is, English is generally head-initial and specifier-initial. Kashaya is generally head-final and specifier-initial. Same with Malagasy and Hixkaryana.

It was proposed that the theory of syntax, coupled with a universal set of parameters can account for the entirety of the world’s languages. That is, suppose that there is a finite number of “switches,” and each language has a unique cumulative setting for each switch. This was (and still is) a popular idea. Even if it’s not entirely correct, it’s still a very handy way to think about language variation.

 

Parametric Variation (length: 2m 39s) Credit: Sydney Pritchard

Recap and a look forward

This ends the first part of this book. We’ve built a theory of syntax: X-bar theory. We did so by looking at data, and thinking about how that data tells us. In the end, we decided that the X-bar schema was an efficient way to capture observed patterns in syntactic structures. It is worth reflecting again on what the benefit of the X-bar schema is. It is no longer necessary for us (as researchers) to try to figure out the “VP” rule, or the “NP” rule, because in fact, they’re the same rule! It’s just the X-bar tree.

Even more, consider the task of language acquisition. Every baby is confronted with a huge challenge: acquiring the intricacies of language. That challenge is greatly simplified if the baby intrinsically knows that everything they’re hearing conforms to X-bar syntax. The baby doesn’t have to learn about all the different things that can go in VP, nor all the different things that can go in NP. For the most part, the baby doesn’t have to figure out the constituency of the words they are hearing, because the constituency is essentially dictated by the X-bar schema (in most cases). This greatly simplifies what a baby needs to learn to acquire a language — any language. All they need to figure out (besides the words) are the parameters. Is the language head-initial or head-final? Is the language specifier-initial or specifier-final?

From here on out, we’re going to stick with the X-bar schema; we won’t make any more changes to the structure that we use. Going forward, we’re going to start talking about manipulating structure. What happens when things start to move around?

Key Takeaways

  • Intermediate levels are found across all phrases.
  • The X-bar schema is empirically motivated by looking at constituency
  • The X-bar schema defines four positions: head, complement, specifier, adjunct.
  • Complements and adjuncts can be empirically distinguished through three tests.

Advanced

The X-bar schema only permits maximally binary branching trees. That is, according to the X-bar schema, a node can have at most two daughters. It can have fewer than two daughters, i.e., one or no daughters. But it cannot have three daughters.

In light of this constraint, we should revisit two of our phrase structure rules which seem to require a node to have three daughters. Recall our rules for coordination:

  • XP –> XP conj XP
  • X’ –> X’ conj X’
  • X –> X conj X

It’s not immediately clear how to map these rules into X’-syntax. Is there any way to demonstrate constituency that is consistent with binary branching structures? It turns out that there are a few tests that suggest an “asymmetric” constituent structure. Consider the following minimal, which involve (apparent) rightward movement of part of a coordinated element.

\setcounter{ExNo}{26}  \ex. \a. Patrick ate an apple yesterday, and also a banana. \b. *Patrick ate an apple and, yesterday, also a banana.

This data show that the conjunction and groups together with the second conjunct, not the first.

Additional data comes from what is called Left-Branch Extraction. The basic observation is that sometimes you can move (something inside of) the leftmost part of a coordinate, but nothing in the rightmost part. An illustrative example comes from Japanese.[3] (The underlines indicate where the first word has moved from.)

\setcounter{ExNo}{27}  \ex. \ag. ringo-o Taro-wa [{\underline{\hspace{10pt}}} san ko] to [banana-o ni hon] tabeta\\ apple-\textsc{acc} Taro-\textsc{top} {} three \textsc{cl} and banana-\textsc{acc} two \textsc{cl} ate\\ \trans `Taro ate three apples and two bananas.' \bg. *banana-o Taro-wa [ringo-o san ko] to [{\underline{\hspace{10pt}}} ni hon] tabeta\\ apple-\textsc{acc} Taro-\textsc{top} apple-\textsc{acc} three \textsc{cl} and {} two \textsc{cl} ate\\ \trans `Taro ate three apples and two bananas.'

While an analysis of Left Branch Extraction is beyond the scope of this class, what we probably should conclude is that in coordination, the head of the coordination, i.e., and forms a constituent with the two element, to the exclusion of the first. It’s possible therefore to translate our phrase structure rules for coordination above into the following X’ compliant trees.

Rendered by QuickLaTeX.com

This tree treats the first coordinate as a specifier, and the second as a complement. And crucially, it groups the head of ConjP together with the second coordinate.


  1. Note that the term "adverb" is a bit misleading: this aren't "adding" to the "verb".
  2. FYI Complement is spelled with an 'e'. It is not compliment.
  3. Bošković, Željko. "On the coordinate structure constraint, across-the-board-movement, phases, and labeling." Recent developments in phase theory (2020): 133-182.
definition

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License

The Science of Syntax Copyright © by John Gluckman is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book